Intelligent Design (ID) is a scientific research program embraced by a relatively small but growing group of scientists and other academics (called ‘design theorists’) who argue that: ‘intelligent agency, as an aspect of scientific theory making, has more explanatory power in accounting for the specified, and sometimes irreducible complexity of some physical systems, including biological entities, and/or the existence of the universe as a whole, than the blind forces of. . . matter.’[1] That is, intelligent design is a better explanation for entities exhibiting complex specified information (CSI)[2] than are appeals to the inherent capacities of nature (i.e. chance and/or physical necessity). ID suggests that the world contains objects that exhaust the explanatory resources of undirected natural causes, and can only be adequately explained by recourse to intelligent causation. For example, according to biochemist Michael J. Behe:
it’s been the very progress of science itself that has made intelligent design plausible. Fifty years ago much less was known about the cell, and it was much easier then to think that Darwinian evolution was true. But with the discovery of more and more complexity at the foundation of life, the idea of intelligent design has gained strength. That trend is continuing. As science pushes on, the complexity of the cell is not getting less; on the contrary, it is getting much greater.[3]
Design theorists have claimed that intelligent design can be inferred from:
Philosopher Francis J. Beckwith reports that: ‘ID proponents have developed highly sophisticated arguments, have had their work published by prestigious presses and in academic journals, have aired their views among critics in the corridors of major universities and institutions, and have been recognized by leading periodicals, both academic and non-academic.’[9]
Perhaps the best single volume introduction to intelligent design theory is Science and Evidence for Design in the Universe (Ignatius Press, 2000), a collection of densely argued papers by leading design theorists biochemist Michael J. Behe, mathematician and philosopher William A. Dembski & philosopher of science Stephen C. Meyer. [Click on cover picture to purchase. Cover picture’s from www.amazon.co.uk] |
‘Intelligent design theory. . . says nothing about the Bible.’[11]
Oxford zoologist Richard Dawkins lumps ID together with ‘creation science’, calling ID a ‘euphemism for creationists.’[12] Leonard Krishtalka notoriously slighted ID as ‘creationism in a cheap tuxedo.’[13] This rhetorical slight of hand is a consistent feature of Darwinian apologetics: ‘anyone critical of Darwinian evolution risks being stereotyped as a strict believer in biblical creation.’[14] Paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould asserted that the only dissenters from macroevolution are ‘protestant fundamentalists who believe that every word of the Bible must be literally true.’[15] In reality: ‘some of the strongest critics of Darwin’s theory are scientists who happen to be non-fundamentalist Protestants, Catholics, or Jews (as well as agnostics).’[16] As John Angus Campbell says:
The ID movement, comprising as it does academics, scientists, philosophers, humanist educators, and interested laypeople, is certainly not the same, except for purposes of histrionic exaggeration, as the young-earth, six-literal-days ‘creation science’ of the past. . . In the ambiance of ID’s ‘broad tent’. . . one will find persons of many philosophic perspectives and metaphysical commitments.[17]
Historian of science Ronald L. Numbers observes that proponents of evolution tend to conflate ID and creationism: ‘They see intelligent design as little more than gussied up creationism, despite the significant differences.’[18] However, as Dr. Benjamin Wiker observes: ‘intelligent design theorists who are Christians are very careful to distinguish themselves from creationists.’[19] This is not because design theorists necessarily accept Darwinist’s low opinion of ‘creationism’. Indeed, some design theorists are also ‘creationists’; just as some evolutionists are also atheists. However, ID is not ‘creationism’ (anymore than evolution, as opposed to naturalistic evolution or Darwinism, is inherently atheistic). The story told by ID:
veers away from the usual theistic evolutionary story (‘based on the evidence, theistic scientists are now concluding that God worked through evolution’) and from the classic creation science tale (‘scientists are recognizing that Genesis is literally true after all’).[20]
Hence the need to draw clear lines of demarcation and to avoid making criticisms of the former that, whether sound or unsound, could only apply to the latter.
Design theorist, philosopher and mathematician William A. Dembski is at pains to stress that ID is not ‘creationism’ as popularly understood:
the design theorists’ critique of Darwinism in no way hinges on the Genesis account of creation. . . The design theorists’ beef is not with evolutionary change per se, but with the claim by Darwinists that all such change is driven by purely naturalistic processes. . . the design theorists’ critique of Darwinism begins with Darwinism’s failure as an empirically adequate scientific theory, and not with its supposed incompatibility with some system of religious belief.[21]
Design theorist Professor Phillip E. Johnson stresses: ‘I am not a defender of creation-science. . . The essential point of creation has nothing to do with the timing or the mechanism the Creator chose to employ, but with the element of design or purpose.’[22] Johnson’s 1989 ‘Position Paper on Darwinism’ explains: ‘The truly fundamental question is whether the natural world is the product of a pre-existing intelligence and whether we exist for a purpose that we did not invent ourselves.’[23] Johnson points out that:
Creationists are not necessarily Genesis literalists or believers in a young earth, nor do they necessarily reject ‘evolution’ in all senses of that highly manipulable term. A creationist is simply a person who believes. . . that the living world is the product of an intelligent and purposeful Creator rather than merely a combination of [unintended] chance events and impersonal natural laws.[24]
In Johnson’s sense of the word, theistic evolutionists (who accept evolution as God’s method of creation via secondary causes) are creationists, and a creationist needn’t even be a theist. They certainly don’t need to accept any of the various interpretations of the Genesis creation story.[25] They simply need to accept the metaphysical hypothesis of design.
Design theorists additionally accept design as a scientific inference to the best explanation: ‘design theorists do not defend their position by appealing to esoteric knowledge, special revelation, or religious authority. They make philosophical and scientific arguments whose merits should be assessed by their soundness. . .’[26] Dr. Thomas Woodward, author of Doubts about Darwin: A History of Intelligent Design, repudiates the claim that ID is motivated by religious premises:
hearing how key Design advocates came to their current view, it became clear that their entry into the movement stemmed from intellectual or scientific – not religious – reasons. . . Several of the founders frequently relate a vivid tale of how they previously had assumed the validity of Darwinian scenarios and were later shocked to discover major weaknesses in the case for Darwinism. Typically this intellectual epiphany leads to further reading and research, which cements the new radical doubt about the theory’s plausibility.[27]
ID suggests that the religiously unencumbered concept of intelligent design is a better and more fruitful explanation of certain biological and physical evidence than the hypothesis that natural regularities and chance (whether or not these causes are themselves created) are responsible.
‘ID is a research program whose inferences support, and are consistent with, some belief in a higher intelligence or deity; it is not a creed that contains belief in a specific deity as one of its tenets.’ – Francis J. Beckwith[29]
While a design paradigm has historically dominated cosmology and biology (from Anaxagorus, Socrates, Plato and Aristotle through to Newton and Paley), design arguments have also been a part of natural theology, the philosophical project of providing evidence for God’s existence. However, design arguments can only provide part of the evidence for God.[30] The ID movement recognizes this fact and insists upon distinguishing between arguing for intelligent design and arguing for divine design (a fact that critics of ID often obfuscate). Behe writes:
my argument is limited to design itself; I strongly emphasize that it is not an argument for the existence of a benevolent God, as Paley’s was. I hasten to add that I myself do believe in a benevolent God, and I recognize that philosophy and theology may be able to extend the argument. But a scientific argument for design in biology does not reach that far. Thus while I argue for design, the question of the identity of the designer is left open. . . as regards the identity of the designer, modern ID theory happily echoes Isaac Newton’s phrase, hypothesis non fingo.[31]
ID argues that there are natural entities that cannot reasonably be explained by chance and/or physical necessity, and only then infers, on the basis of experience, that the best explanation of these features of reality is intelligent causation (ID is not an ‘argument from ignorance’). Whether the intelligence in question is God is yet a further question: ‘detecting design. . . does not implicate any particular intelligence.’[32]
Failure to appreciate the distinction between intelligent design and divine design has contributed to the scientific establishment throwing out the design paradigm as essentially tied to belief in God when it was not. After all, one could accept intelligent design and attribute it to the activity of angels, demons, Plato’s finite god (the Demiurge), the gods of Egyptian, Greek or Norse polytheism, or to aliens, rather than to God (hence it is logically possible for an atheist to support ID[33]).
The plain truth is that ‘Intelligent design is not a form of natural theology’[34]; and while every design argument for God is an argument for intelligent design, not every argument for intelligent design need be viewed as an argument for God - at least, not without considerations from outside ID as a scientific theory being brought to bear: ‘intelligent design theory by itself makes no claims about the nature of the designer, and scientists currently working within an intelligent design framework include Protestants, Catholics, Jews, agnostics, and others.’[35] As Benjamin Wiker suggests: ‘from scientific evidence open to all, we can infer that nature has an intelligent designer. Further, we can extend these arguments philosophically, demonstrating that the intelligent designer is God.’[36]
ID obviously has much to contribute to natural theology, in that divine design is a plausible and independently supported candidate for the source of scientifically detectable intelligent design. Theologically speaking, it is interesting to note, given ID’s emphasis on the need to explain the origin of information that the Bible portrays God as creating through his Word or ‘Logos’ (Gen 1:3, John 1:1-3): ‘Of course God did not physically speak and produce sound waves’, writes theologian Terence L. Nichols, ‘But the point is that the word conveys information. Gods act of creating. . . involves the input of specifying information. . .’[37] Likewise, natural theology has much to contribute to ID. The two projects are mutually re-enforcing. On the one hand, ID furnishes natural theology with the basis for powerful new versions of the design argument. On the other hand, anyone who is already impressed by natural theology should be kindly predisposed towards ID.
In Laws (Book X) the Greek philosopher Plato observed that: ‘all things do become, have become and will become, some by nature, some by art [intelligent design], and some by chance.’[38] ID constitutes a scientific paradigm based upon acknowledging all of the explanatory possibilities listed by Plato and the existence of reliable criteria legitimating evidentially motivated inferences to the explanatory superiority of intelligent design (‘art’) in certain well-defined circumstances, thereby freeing science to follow the evidence wherever it leads.
(Plato, from The School of Athens by Raphael[39])
The ‘open’ philosophy of science[40] adopted by ID is in stark contrast to the approach of those who work within the explanatory confines of metaphysical or even ‘methodological’ naturalism. According to Richard Dawkins: ‘The kind of explanation we come up with must not contradict the laws of physics. Indeed it will make use of the laws of physics, and nothing more than the laws of physics.’[41] Richard Lewontin openly admits:
It is not that the methods. . . of science somehow compel us to accept a material explanation of the. . . world, but, on the contrary, that we are forced by our. . . adherence to material causes to create. . . a set of concepts that produce material explanations, no matter how counterintuitive, no matter how mystifying. . .[42]
But as William A. Dembski notes, here: ‘we are dealing with a naturalistic metaphysic that shapes and controls what theories of biological origins are permitted on the playing field in advance of any discussion or weighing of evidence.’[43] And as philosopher of science Del Ratzsch observes:
The scientific attitude has usually been characterised as a commitment to following the evidence wherever it leads. That does not look like promising ammunition for someone pushing an official policy of refusing to allow science to follow evidence to. . . design no matter what the evidence turns out to be. . . it commits science to either having to deliberately ignore major (possibly even observable) features of the material realm or having to refrain from even considering the obvious and only workable explanation, should it turn out that those features clearly resulted from [intelligent] activity. . . any imposed policy of naturalism in science has the potential not only of eroding any self-correcting capability of science but of preventing science from reaching certain truths. Any imposed policy of methodological naturalism will have precisely the same potential consequences.[44]
If philosophical naturalism is true, then a policy of methodological naturalism cannot possibly subvert the truth seeking intent of science; but perhaps philosophical naturalism is not true, and perhaps science should operate without making any assumptions that might force it to ignore reality.
Science & It’s Limits: The Natural Sciences in Christian Perspective by Professor Del Ratzsch (Apollos, 2000) is a readable and comprehensive introduction to the philosophy of science. |
At the very least, the rule of ‘methodological naturalism’ should be stated so as to make a distinction between recognising intelligent design and supernatural design: ‘in science’, says Larry Witham, ‘the question is not between finding natural causes or supernatural causes, but between natural and intelligent ones.’[45] (It should be noted that this distinction – which I have called the distinction between ‘hard-line’ and ‘soft’ methodological naturalism – sidesteps the question of whether intelligence is by its very nature a supernatural reality.[46] Hence, one could think of this distinction as a methodological distinction allowing ID to stake out the broadest possible ‘tent’ by leaving the ontological nature of intelligence outside of its core commitments.)
Besides: ‘recent studies in the philosophy of science have confirmed. . . that philosophically neutral criteria that can define science narrowly enough to disqualify theories of creation or design without also disqualifying Darwinism and/or other materialistic evolutionary theories on identical grounds do not exist.’[47] And as philosopher of science J.P. Moreland points out:
some branches of science, including SETI, archaeology, forensic science, psychology and sociology, use personal agency and various internal states of agents (desires, willings, intentions, awareness, thought, beliefs) as part of their description of the causal entities, processes, events or actions cited as explanations for certain phenomena. . . Thus there is nothing non-scientific about appealing to personal agency and the like in a scientific explanation[48]
Indeed, many sciences depend upon detecting intelligence: ‘notably forensic science, artificial intelligence. . . cryptography, archaeology and the Search for Extraterrestrial Intelligence [SETI].’[49] ID simply suggests: ‘that we extend these insights, which have proved so fruitful in other fields, to the world of the natural sciences.’[50]
Darwinist Michael Ruse acknowledges that: ‘It would indeed be very odd were I and others to simply characterize “science” as something which, by definition, is based on (methodological) naturalistic philosophy and hence excludes [intelligent design].’[51] In a speech given at the annual meeting of the American Association for the Advancement of Science in 1993, Ruse conceded that: ‘philosophically one should be sensitive to what I think history shows, namely, that evolution. . . involves making certain a priori or metaphysical assumptions, which at some level cannot be proven empirically.’[52] Little wonder, then, that: ‘A central claim of the ID movement is that if science education is to be other than state-sponsored propaganda, a clear and principled distinction must be drawn between empirical science and the materialist philosophy that drives contemporary Darwinian theories of biological origins.’[53]
According to design theorists, developments in information theory mean that there now exist ‘well-defined methods that, on the basis of observational features of the world, are capable of reliably distinguishing intelligent causes from undirected natural causes.’[54] Hence William A. Dembski defines intelligent design as: ‘the science that studies how to detect intelligence.’[55] Thus, according to Dembski, ID is properly formulated as a theory of information:
intelligent design is therefore not the study of intelligent causes per se but of informational pathways induced by intelligent causes. As a result intelligent design presupposes neither a creator nor miracles. . . it detects intelligence without speculating about the nature of the intelligence. . .[56]
As Geoscientist Marcus R. Ross explained in a presentation before the Geological Society of America: ‘ID is classified as a philosophically minimalistic position, asserting that real design exists in nature and is empirically detectable by the methods of science.’[57] It is this minimal metaphysical baggage that keeps ID firmly within the realm of science.
Scientists who allow a commitment to naturalistic explanations to predetermine their explanatory options when faced with empirical evidence of intelligent design are, to use an example from physicist Robert Kaita, like researchers stubbornly committed to finding a naturalistic explanation for ‘crop-circles’:
mysterious patterns were found in wheat fields taking the form of large, distinct geometric patterns. . . speculation ran from intelligent causes, such as ingenious pranksters, or the perennial favorite, extraterrestrial beings, to natural phenomena. Finally a couple of men admitted responsibility and revealed that their equipment consisted of very large versions of the stylus and string that people have been using to make geometric figures since antiquity. . . In spite of this unequivocal evidence for design, some [people] persisted in suggesting highly improbable natural causes.[58]
Kaita draws a moral from this episode: ‘We need always to keep in mind two separate questions: how well does the evidence support design? And, Are we predisposed to reject design apart from the evidence? The first is a scientific question. The second is a philosophical question.’[60] For those who wish to exclude the possibility of intelligent design a priori, ‘the motive is based not on “just the facts” but on philosophical prejudice’.[61]
Such philosophical prejudice frequently results in question-begging and circular arguments. Philosopher of science Stephen C. Meyer calculates that: ‘the probability of constructing a rather short functional protein at random [is] so small as to be effectively zero. . .’[62] If we ask Dawkins for the best explanation of the complex molecules of life he says: ‘Nobody knows how it happened but, somehow, without violating the laws of physics and chemistry, a molecule arose that just happened to have the property of self-copying – a replicator.’[63] If no one knows what happened, how does Dawkins know that what happened didn’t ‘violate the laws of physics and chemistry’? He simply begs the question. Here, at least, is a frank admission of ignorance: ‘I would have to be more of a chemist that I am to know how likely it is that you are going to get such molecules,’ says Dawkins, ‘I don’t know how difficult it would be to achieve that chemically.’[64] Consider how significant it is to find Dawkins, who accuses theists of blind faith and who exhorts people to always ask, ‘What kind of evidence is there for that?’,[65] believing in what he calls the ‘sine qua non’[66] of evolution without empirical evidence! Benjamin Wiker comments that Dawkins’: ‘lapse into an irrational faith in the powers of chance to avoid [intelligent design]. . . is not evidence itself but a telling lapse into a materialist credo quia absurdum est’.[67] Dawkins is not alone in making this sort of leap of faith. Harvard biologist George Wald dismissed a design explanation for life but candidly admitted:
I will not believe that philosophically because I do not want to believe in God. Therefore, I choose to believe in that which I know is scientifically impossible: spontaneous generation [that life arose from non-living matter] arising to evolution.[68]
Phillip E. Johnson complains: ‘The naturalistic evolution of life from prebiotic chemicals and its subsequent naturalistic evolution into complexity. . . is assumed as a matter of first principle. . .’[69] As G. A. Kerkut of the Department of Physiology and Biochemistry at the University of Southampton writes, it is: ‘a matter of faith on the part of the biologist that biogenesis did occur. . .’[70] For scientists like Dawkins and Wald, who reject an ‘open’ philosophy of science, the hypothesis that life ‘just happened’ is a philosophical deduction entailed by the assumption of naturalism. To approach biology without begging-the-question like this does not mean excluding consideration of the theory of abiogenesis, or evolution (as Darwinians exclude consideration of intelligent design). Rather, it means letting the evidence speak for itself and following the evidence wherever it leads.[71]
Johnson observes that: ‘Darwinism is the answer to a specific question that grows out of philosophical naturalism. . . The questions is: How must creation have occurred if we assume that God [or other intelligent designer/s] had nothing to do with it?’[72] Design theorists are more than happy to confirm that neo-Darwinism is the best available answer to that question; but answering that question is not at all the same thing as answering this far more interesting, unbiased and important question: ‘How did creation actually occur?’
To understand what design theorists mean by CSI, imagine a game of scrabble. A long string of random letters drawn from a scrabble bag is complex without being specified - that is, without conforming to a non ad hoc pattern that we haven’t simply read off the object or event in question. A short sequence of letters like ‘this’ or ‘that’ is specified (it conforms to a non ad hoc, independent pattern) without being sufficiently complex to outstrip the capacity of chance to explain this conformity (letters drawn at random from the scrabble bag will occasionally form a short word.) However, this article is both specified (conforming to the independent functional requirements of grammatical English language use) and sufficiently complex (doing so at a level of complexity that makes it unreasonable to attribute this match to dumb luck) to trigger a design inference. It would be unreasonable to suggest that I produced this article by randomly drawing tiles from a scrabble bag!
Philosopher William Lane Craig explains the logic the design inference with a simple illustration:
Bob is given a new car for his birthday. There are millions of license plate numbers, and it is therefore highly unlikely that Bob would get, say, CHT 4271. Yet that plate on his birthday car would occasion no special interest. But suppose Bob, who was born on 8 August 1949 finds BOB 8849 on the license plate of his birthday car. He would be obtuse if he shrugged this off with the comment, ‘Well, it had to have some license plate, and any number is equally improbable. . .’[73]
Bob’s car having the first license plate was complex (unlikely) but it wasn’t noteworthy because it wasn’t specified. Bob’s car having the second license plate was noteworthy because in addition to being complex it was also specified (it matched the independently given pattern of Bob’s name and birth-date). Hence, according to William A. Dembski: ‘given an event, object, or structure, to convince ourselves that it is designed we need to show that it is improbably (i.e. complex) and suitably patterned (i.e. specified).’[74]
It is popularly thought that ‘if you have enough monkeys banging randomly on typewriters they will eventually type the works of William Shakespeare’, but there is a real world limit to the number of ‘monkeys’ available and the time in which they can type. Indeed, I heard about a zoo that put a typewriter in their monkey cage: the monkeys defecated in the typewriter and hit the same key over and over again!
(Monkey picture from ‘Monkey Shakespeare Simulator’[75])
To take the point less literally, the online ‘Monkey Shakespeare Simulator’ uses logged-on computers to simulate an ever-increasing population of ‘monkeys’ randomly typing (on simplified keyboards, at a rate of one day’s typing per second), and compares the results to Shakespeare’s works.[76] As of October 2004, the best result was twenty ‘letters’ (if one includes spaces and full stops) from Coriolanus, after 462,060,000,000 billion billion ‘monkey-years’![77] Getting better results is clearly going to take a lot more monkey-years; but as Dembski would point out, we can’t simply keep giving ourselves free ‘monkey-years’. ‘Just where the probabilities cutoff is can be debated,’ says Dembski, ‘but that there is a probabilistic cutoff beyond which chance becomes an unacceptable explanation is clear.’[78] As Richard Dawkins affirms: ‘We can accept a certain amount of luck in our explanations, but not too much.’[79] In fact, limiting the explanatory capacity of ‘chance’ is crucial to the integrity of science: ‘If we allow ourselves too many “wildcard” bits of information. . . we can explain anything be reference to chance.’[80] Allowing ourselves too many ‘wildcard bits of information’ commits the inflationary fallacy: ‘the problem inherent in the inflationary fallacy is always that it multiplies probabilistic resources in the absence of independent evidence that such resources exist.’[81]
Postulating unlimited probabilistic resources makes it impossible to warrant attributing anything to design. Is Dawkins a good writer or does he simply move his hands over his computer keyboard in the right way by luck? Dawkins’ books could happen by chance, if we assume the existence of sufficiently large probabilistic resources: ‘Unlimited probabilistic resources make bizarre possibilities unavoidable on a grand scale.’[82] Dembski calculates a stringent probability bound of 10-150 based on the number of elementary particles in the universe, the duration of the observable universe and the Plank time.
In Climbing Mount Improbable Richard Dawkins draws a distinction between objects that exhibit evidence of being designed and objects that give the superficial impression that they exhibit evidence of being designed but on closer inspection do not, which he calls ‘designoid’.[83] Dawkins illustrates the concept of being designoid with a hillside that suggests a human profile: ‘Once you have been told, you can just see a slight resemblance to either John or Robert Kennedy. But some don’t see it and it is certainly easy to believe that the resemblance is accidental.’[84] Dawkins contrasts this Kennedy-esque hillside with the four president’s heads carved into Mt. Rushmore in America, which ‘are obviously not accidental: they have design written all over them.’[85]
Although Dawkins defines biology as ‘the study of complicated things that give the appearance of having been designed for a purpose’,[86] he believes that appearances are deceiving. All biological things that appear to be designed are designoid: ‘Designoid objects look designed, so much so that some people – probably, alas, most people – think that they are designed. These people are wrong. . . the true explanation – Darwinian natural selection – is very different.’[87]
Teasing apart Dawkins’ rhetoric is a rewarding hobby. His original illustration of a designoid is of something that gives the superficial impression that it exhibits evidence of being designed. People have to have the resemblance between the hillside and Kennedy pointed out to them, some people ‘don’t see it’[88], and ‘it is certainly easy to believe that the resemblance is accidental.’[89] However, Dawkins wants to convince us that although some biological objects give such a strong appearance of design that ‘most people’[90] intuitively think that they are designed, they are merely designoid. On the face of things, Dawkins’ design/designoid distinction actually supports the majority opinion that life is the product of design. Some natural objects are surely more analogous to Mt. Rushmore than they are to the Kenney-esque hillside. In which case, how does Dawkins justify his confident, universal negative claim (the hardest sort of claim to prove) that absolutely no biological objects are designed, and that any biological object giving the appearance, however strong, of design, is merely ‘designoid’? Indeed, if the paradigm ‘designoid’ object is the Kennedy-esque hillside, then such a broad application of the concept is surely inappropriate. The meaning of Dawkins’ flagship term shifts from ‘things that give the superficial impression that they exhibit clear evidence of being designed, but on closer inspection do not’, to ‘things that give every appearance of being designed, but are not’, thereby exhibiting the logical fallacy of ‘equivocation’.[91]
If Dawkins’ hypothesis is simply, as Alan Keith suggests, that ‘some things that appear to be designed are not in fact designed’[92], what justification does he give for thinking that life only appears to be designed? It’s easy enough to tell design and designoid apart as Dawkins’ introduces the distinction; but how are we to tell design from designoid given his implicit re-definition of these terms? We cannot! Dawkins applies the first distinction on the basis of observational features of the objects in question, but he applies the second distinction on the basis of his commitment to metaphysical naturalism. A consistent, non-question-begging understanding and application of Dawkins’ design/designoid distinction seems to support the conclusion that life is the product of design, and hence of purpose.
Reviewing this criticism of the design/designoid argument[93], Massimo Pigliucci[94] and the members of his graduate class on evolutionary thinking at the University of Tennessee, Knoxville respond that this objection to Dawkins ‘is partly right’.[95] According to Professor Pigliucci et al: ‘Dawkins did choose a bad example, and for fundamentally wrong reasons’[96] when he illustrated the concept of a ‘designoid’ with a hillside that looks a bit like a Kennedy from the right angle. The problem with Dawkins’ analogy, according to Pigliucci et al, is that: ‘The resemblance of the cliff outcropping to a human face is the result of entirely random causes. . . while biological organisms are the outcome of two processes: mutation (which is indeed random) and natural selection (which is anything but random).’[97] Of course, whether or not everything about all biological organisms is the outcome of nothing but these natural forces, one random (mutation) and one non-random (natural selection), is the very point at issue. Pigliucci et al agree with me that ‘Dawkins’ designoids don’t cut it’, but argue that this is because his original illustration provides a poor analogy for the organism producing forces at work in evolution:
Dawkins’ fundamental point can be rescued by simply using a better analogy. There are natural, non-biological, processes that convey the impression of intelligent design and provide us with a more closer parallel to evolution. For example, on many rocky beaches, pebbles are sorted by size going from the waterline towards the interior, in a distinctly non-random pattern. This is not because somebody got all the pebbles out of the ocean, carefully weighed them, and then constructed the beach. Rather, the pattern was created by the joint action of two processes: the (random) action of waves and the (non-random) effects of gravity.[98]
Is this new analogy for ‘designoid’ any better than Dawkins’? No. If anything, it is a worse analogy, because people don’t intuit the presence of design when observing beaches! The sorting of pebbles on a beach simply does not ‘convey the impression of intelligent design’, whereas Dawkins’ Kennedy-esque hillside does at least convey the initial impression of design. Hence Dawkins’ hillside analogy, while it may be a worse analogy for the process of evolution, is the better illustration of the concept of a ‘designoid’, and the pebble-sorting of Pigliucci et al, while it may be a better analogy for evolution, is a worse illustration of the concept of a ‘designoid’! Like Dawkins’, Pigliucci et al provide an illustration that tends to reinforce the intuitive conclusion that the appearance of design in nature is not deceptive.[99]
Philosopher Robert C. Koons observes that: ‘The Western philosophical tradition has bequeathed us two competing metaphysical models: one in which everything is to be explained ultimately in terms of blind and purposeless forces (the materialistic model); and one in which purposefulness is a fundamental and irreducible reality (the teleological model).’[100] The most important question ‘from an epistemological point of view’[101], writes Koons, is this: ‘where should we locate the presumption of truth, and where the burden of proof?’[102] Koons argues that:
There are compelling grounds for placing the burden of proof on the materialistic model. Even stalwart Darwinists like Richard Dawkins admit that the defining task of biology is to explain the existence of things that appear to be designed. Cicero, in On the Nature of the Gods, Book II, reports Aristotle’s cave analogy: if a group of people had spent all of their lives underground and then emerged on the surface, they would be bound to think of the biologically rich world they discovered there to be the product of intelligence. Only familiarity dulls our sense of wonder at the craftsmanship of nature.
In his essay on the Intellectual Powers of Man, eighteenth-century Scottish philosopher Thomas Reid cites the capacity to recognize the signs of intelligent agency as part of the basic equipment of the human mind. . . When this basic faculty of intelligence-recognition considers the machinery of living things, the clear answer it delivers is yes, there is intelligence and purposefulness displayed in such machinery.[103]
While ‘the natural deliverances of our sense of intelligence can be defeated’[104], says Koons, ‘there is an undeniable burden of proof that must first be assumed.’[105] Question-begging assertions like those made by Dawkins, Lewontin and Wald fail to defeat the presumption of truth that should be accorded to belief in design.
Ironically enough, Dawkins’ discussion of the design/designoid distinction actually illustrates intelligent design methodology. Dawkins argues that while ‘a rock can weather into the shape of a nose seen from a certain vantage point’,[106] [cf. figure 2] such a rock is designoid (i.e. it is not clearly the produce of intelligent design, because it is easy to believe that ‘the resemblance is accidental.’[107]) Mt. Rushmore [cf. figure 1], on the other hand, is obviously not designoid: ‘Its four heads are clearly designed,’[108] argues Dawkins, because: ‘The sheer number of details [i.e. the amount of complexity] in which the Mount Rushmore faces resemble the real things [i.e. the complexity fits four independent specifications] is too great to have come about by chance.’[109] In terms of mere possibility, says Dawkins: ‘The weather could have done the same job. . . But of all the possible ways of weathering a mountain, only a tiny minority would be speaking likenesses of four particular human beings.’[110] Hence: ‘Even if we didn’t know the history of Mount Rushmore, we’d estimate the odds against its four heads being carved by accidental weathering as astronomically high. . .’[111]
Figure 2. An accident of nature: President John F. Kennedy’s profile formed by shadow cast by a large rock in Hawaii.[112]
In other words, Mt. Rushmore is obviously the product of intelligent design because it exhibits what information theorists call specified complexity, whereas the hill-side is not obviously the product of intelligent design because it does not exhibit specified complexity: ‘it is certainly easy to believe that the resemblance [i.e. the hill’s conformation to a specification] is accidental [i.e. is not complex].’[113]
The significant point here is that Dawkins’ own design detection criteria is obviously a pre-theoretic version of the design detection criteria elaborated by William A. Dembski in such books as The Design Inference (Cambridge, 1999) and No Free Lunch, (Rowman & Littlefield, 2001).
Mathematician & Philosopher Professor William A. Dembski has broken new ground in information theory with his work on the design inference from ‘specified complexity’. Among the most scholarly presentations of this work are: The Design Inference (Cambridge University Press, 1999), where Dembski explicates his ‘explanatory filter’ & No Free Lunch (Rowman & Littlefield, 2002) which applies the insights of The Design Inference within biology.
Returning to the beach example suggested by Pigliucci et al, let us ask the question: ‘How could pebbles on a beach convey clear evidence of intelligent design’? A random spread of pebbles would not do the trick. Such a distribution of pebbles may be complex, but it lacks specificity. Nor would having the pebbles ‘sorted by size going from the waterline towards the interior, in a distinctly non-random pattern’ do the trick. Such a distribution of pebbles is specific (‘distinctly non-random’) but not particularly complex. What definitely would tip us off to the presence of design is if the pebbles were arranged to spell out a message such as: ‘Hello and welcome to the seaside. We hope that you will enjoy this beach.’ Such an arrangement, which exhibits an independent specification at very low probability, would obviously imply intelligent design. Such an arrangement of matter not only ‘looks a bit like it might be designed at first glance’, like Dawkins’ hillside, but gives every appearance of being designed. If one cannot infer design from such an arrangement of matter, then matter simply cannot be arranged in a way that clearly signals design! Only a dogmatic commitment to design-free explanations would prevent one from saying that such a pattern was the result of design.
It’s all very well to observe that some things that don’t require explanation in terms of design can give the superficial impression that they do require such an explanation (e.g. Dawkins’ Kennedy-esque hillside), to call such things ‘designoid’, and to draw the moral that we should take care about saying that something requires explanation in terms of design. It is quite another thing to observe Mt. Rushmore, or pebbles on a beach that spell ‘We hope you enjoy this beach’, and to assert that this pattern is ‘designoid’! And yet, in effect, that is what Dawkins does with the evidence for design.
However it is illustrated, the meaning of the key term in Dawkins’ argument surreptitiously evolves under our noses. It begins life meaning ‘something that gives a superficial impression of design’ and ends up meaning ‘a thing that gives every indication of being the product of design, but isn’t.’ Dawkins needs ‘designoid’ to carry this latter meaning because he accepts that: ‘When a biologist looks at particular organs or organisms. . . what he sees is a machine, which has every indication of being designed for a purpose.’[114] However, such an equivocation turns a useful distinction into an empirically vacuous concept that begs the question by smuggling in the metaphysical assumption that intelligence is incapable of outperforming the design-producing resources of nature in such a way as to leave reliable, empirically detectable indicators of its activity. Yet when Dawkins is not concerned with design-proofing biology, he holds that intelligence is capable of outperforming the design-producing resources of nature in such a way as to leave reliable, empirically detectable indicators of its activity. Indeed, he employs a version of Dembski’s ‘Design Filter’, motivating the inference to design in the presence of specified complexity.
The ‘Design Filter’ elaborated by Dawkins and Dembski is only a positive test for design. Suppose an artist carefully sculpts a hillside by cleverly mimicking natural weathering so as to produce a profile vaguely like that of a man. The design filter would not detect the activity of intelligence in that hillside. As far as the filter is concerned, the hillside is, at most, designoid. It might be the product of design, it might superficially look like objects that the filter would attribute to design, but the filter gives us no reason to think that it is the product of design because the hillside, while complex, is not specified. On the other hand, if the hillside in question were carved into a detailed (i.e. specific) picture of four American presidents, then the filter would detect design, because such a pattern is both complex and specified. The filter can’t rule design out, but it can rule it in.
The basic physical laws of nature are ‘finely tuned’, or specified, in the sense that if they were only a little different that they in fact are, then the existence of intelligent life would be impossible. This is a fact that many scientists and philosophers take to indicate design - even if they feel uncomfortable with such an implication. As Stephen Hawking once admitted: ‘The odds against a universe like ours emerging out of something like the big bang are enormous. . . I think clearly there are religious implications. . . But I think most scientists prefer to shy away from the religious side of it.’[116] Shying away from a conclusion supported by evidence is hardly a scientific attitude to adopt.
According to Massimo Pigliucci: ‘Should we conclusively determine that the probability of existence of our universe is infinitesimally small, and should we fail to explain why physical constants have assumed the quantities that we observe, the possibility of a designed universe would have to be considered seriously.’[117] Hence, in discussing the fine-tuning of the cosmos, Pigliucci lays down what amounts to a pre-theoretic version of Dembski’s explanatory filter, which infers design when an independent specification (e.g. the set of physical laws required by a life sustaining universe) is exhibited at sufficiently low probability. Pigliucci and design theorists differ on whether we can infer that our universe is the product of design, but at least there would appear to be agreement on the criteria for making such a judgement. Settling the question one-way or the other is a matter of evidence.
Richard Dawkins fails to make the connection between specified complexity as a hallmark of intelligent design and the issue of cosmic fine-tuning, but as has already been observed, he clearly accepts the same design-detection criteria as Pigliucci and Dembski. Moreover, in establishing CSI as a hallmark of intelligent design, Dawkins provides an excellent analogy for understanding cosmic fine-tuning: ‘Of all the unique and, with hindsight equally improbable, positions of the combination lock,’ observes Dawkins, ‘only one opens the lock. . . The uniqueness of the arrangement. . . that opens the safe, [has] nothing to do with hindsight. It is specified in advance.’[118] According to Dawkins, the best explanation of an open safe is not that someone got lucky, but that someone knew the specific and complex combination required to open it. But isn’t the ‘fine-tuning’ of the universe discovered by cosmologists analogous to Dawkins’ example of a cracked combination lock?
Douglas Adams, author of The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy, thought he had a knockdown response to the ‘fine-tuning’ argument, likening it to a puddle of water arguing that, since the dip in the ground it inhabited seemed to fit it so well, the dip must have been created with its existence in mind: ‘This is. . . an interesting hole I find myself in – fits me rather neatly, doesn’t it? In fact it fits me staggeringly well, must have been made to have me in it!’[119] While this analogy makes for a nice piece of humour, as a rebuttal of the fine-tuning argument it is deeply flawed. Water will fit any shape hole – the fit between the hole and the water can be explained wholly by reference to the nature of water. However, life will not fit just any old environment. The fit between our cosmic environment and life cannot be explained wholly by reference to the nature of life: ‘In reviewing the physical laws and the numerical values of fundamental constants, one encounters a remarkable precision in these values such that only small changes in the fundamental constants. . . would yield a universe without galaxies, starts, atoms or even nuclei, and consequently, without the capacity for life.’[120] As Moreland and Craig note: ‘An observer who has evolved within the universe should regard it as highly probable that he will find the basic conditions of the universe fine-tuned for his existence; but he should not infer that it is therefore highly probable that such a fine-tuned universe exists at all.’[121]
Moreland and Craig illustrate the sense in which the fine-tuning of the universe is a highly improbable fact:
Take a sheet of paper and place upon it a red dot. That dot represents our universe. Now alter slightly one or more of the finely tuned constants and physical quantities which have been the focus of our attention. As a result we have a description of another universe, which we may represent by a new dot in the proximity of the first. If that new set of constants and quantities describes a life-permitting universe, make it a red dot; if it describes a universe that is life prohibiting, make it a blue dot. Now repeat the procedure arbitrarily many times until the sheet is filled with dots. One winds up with a sea of blue with only a few pin-points of red.[122]
The hypothetical question of whether or not universes are possible that have wholly different physical variables but are life permitting is irrelevant to the fine-tuning argument. Imagine a fly resting on a large, blank area on a wall:
A single shot is fired, and the bullet strikes the fly. Now even if the rest of the wall outside the blank area is covered with flies, such that a randomly fired bullet would probably hit one, nevertheless it remains highly improbable that a single, randomly fired bullet would strike the solitary fly within the large, blank area. In the same way, we need only concern ourselves with the universes represented on our sheet in order to determine the probability of the existence of a life-permitting universe.[123]
In the case of Dawkins’ cracked combination lock what calls for a teleological explanation is not merely that an event of small probability has taken place (other sequences of number dials are equally improbable), but the fact that this small probability event is specified (as the sequence that opens the lock). Likewise, in the case of cosmic fine-tuning, what calls out for explanation in terms of design is not merely that an event of small probability has taken place (the existence of a particular set of physical laws), but the fact that this event is specified (as the set necessary for a life sustaining universe). Indeed, the fine-tuning of the universe is like cracking a safe with multiple combination locks, one lock for each cosmic parameter: The matter-anti-matter balance ‘had to be accurate to one part in ten billion for the universe to arise.’[124] The expansion rate of the universe from the big bang had to be accurate to one part in 1060, while the force of gravity itself required fine-tuning to one part in 1040.[125] If the strong nuclear force were 2 percent weaker protons and neutrons wouldn’t stick together. If it were 0.3 percent stronger hydrogen (a crucial component of biological systems) could not exist.[126] Oxford physicist Roger Penrose calculated that the original phase-space volume required such exact fine-tuning that the ‘Creator’s aim must have been [precise] to an accuracy of one part in 1010(123).’[127] Penrose was only speaking poetically of the ‘Creator’s aim’, but this sort of data is in fact best explained by the existence of a real Creator. Finely tuned improbabilities compound one another until the overall improbability of cosmic fine-tuning being a fluke becomes unimaginably high. Don N. Page[128] of the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton, N.J., calculates the odds against the formation of our universe at one in 10,000,000,000124! As Fred Hoyle complained: ‘A common sense interpretation of the facts suggests that a superintellect has monkeyed with physics.’[129]
Some cosmologists attempt to avoid this conclusion by positing the existence of a large number of universes (perhaps an infinite number), each with a different set of laws. However, what guarantees that all these universes have different laws is a mystery. Stephen Clark comments:
It is a mark of desperation that some atheistical materialists have chosen to believe in infinite arrays of universes. . . rather than believe instead that this well-adapted world is founded on intelligence. . . explaining away this world by saying that all worlds happen (which does not follow anyway merely from there being, we fantasize, an infinite array of worlds) merely enlarges the problem – and destroys the basis of all explanation (since we could not, on those terms, be right to be surprised at anything, including Pratchett’s Discworld).[130]
The ‘many worlds hypothesis’ commits the inflationary fallacy, of multiplying our explanatory resources without an independent reason for doing so, on a grand scale. The best explanation of cosmic fine-tuning is that an intelligence took careful ‘aim’ with the purpose of producing a life-sustaining universe. When we submit the scientific evidence of cosmic fine-tuning to the design-detection criteria accepted by scientists like Dawkins and Pigliucci we find that the evidence supports the hypothesis of intelligent design.
Within biology, ‘intelligent design is a theory of biological origins and development.’[131] Design theorists claim that the current dominance of neo-Darwinian theory is a function of the pool of live explanatory options being artificially restricted by an unjustified methodological constraint, namely, the philosophical presupposition that natural sciences should only explain things in terms of the inherent capacities of nature (whether or not those capacities are themselves designed). Design theorists argue for a more ‘open philosophy of science’, and insist that the important question is not whether neo-Darwinism is the best explanation given a ban on mentioning intelligent agency, but whether it is the best explanation, full stop. Design theorists argue: ‘that once hypotheses positing Intelligent Design are allowed into the pool of live options, then the explanatory superiority of the neo-Darwinian theory is no longer apparent. On the contrary, its deficiencies, particularly in the explanatory power of its mechanisms of random mutation and natural selection, stand in stark relief.’[132]
When we examine the chemical basis of life we find highly complex contingent arrangements of matter that are specified by their biological functionality. According to Dawkins: ‘Complicated things have some quality, specifiable in advance, that is highly unlikely to have been acquired by random chance alone. In the case of living things, the quality that is specified in advance is. . . the ability to propagate genes in reproduction.’[133] These complex systems cannot be explained by Darwin’s theory of evolution, for the simple reason that they must exist before anything can evolve. As Dawkins says: ‘[For evolution to occur] you need raw materials that can self-replicate. . . The sine qua non [that without which]. . . is self-replication.’[134] Pigliucci et al correctly observe that ‘what is needed for a naturalistic theory of origins is that the first replicators were simple enough to originate randomly.’[135] On the naturalistic hypothesis the first replicators have to be simple enough to originate randomly because natural selection cannot explain the origin of anything that is a precondition of natural selection – and replicators are a pre-condition of natural selection.
In a telling letter to Philosophy Now magazine (August/September 2004) Antony Flew discussed ‘the limits of the negative theological implications of Darwin’s Theory of Evolution by Natural Selection.’ Quoting from Darwin, Flew notes that the theory of evolution by natural selection does not account for the origin of life, and observes that ‘Probably Darwin himself believed that life was miraculously breathed into that primordial form of not always consistently reproducing life by God. . .’[136] Flew also notes that:
the evidential situation of natural (as opposed to revealed) theology has been transformed in the more than fifty years since Watson and Crick won the Nobel Prize for their discovery of the double helix structure of DNA. It has become inordinately difficult even to begin to think about constructing a naturalistic theory of the evolution of that first reproducing organism.[137]
The idea that the pre-requisites of evolution could simply ‘arise’, perhaps from some ‘warm little pond’ of chemicals as Darwin hypothesized, is known as abiogenesis, from the Greek a (without), bios (life) and ginomai (to form). The concept is popularly known today under the rubric of the hypothetical ‘primal soup’, and simply means the supposed naturalistic origin of life from non-life. For example, Isaac Asimov confidently asserts: ‘molecules in the ocean grew gradually more complicated until, eventually, some molecule was somehow formed that could bring about the organization of simpler molecules into another molecule just like itself. With that, life began. . . gradually evolving to the present state of affairs . . .’[138] The way Asimov presents it, the naturalistic origin of life sounds like established history. But as Flew’s comments indicate, it isn’t. A recent New Scientist cover story on ‘The 10 Biggest Mysteries of Life’ (New Scientist, 4th September 2004) included the question ‘How did life begin?’ as one of the ‘biggest unanswered questions’ in biology. As Alan Hayward says of abiogenesis: ‘It all sounds so simple, and so plausible – as long as you know nothing about microbiology.’[139]
The concept of abiogenesis was originally held by ancient Greek thinkers such as Anaximander and Aristotle, and was revived in the mid-twentieth century when Stanley Miller and Harold Urey recreated in the laboratory what they believed to be an accurate representation of the early earth’s atmosphere, and managed (whilst mostly producing oils and tars) to produce some amino acids by passing an electric spark through their mixture of gases. If the extrapolation from this experiment to the viability of the naturalistic origin of life from non-life were sound, one could still ask: ‘What accounts for the existence of a “primal soup” with the correct ‘recipe’ for life?’ The answer, as Benjamin Wiker points out, would track back to the finely tuned laws of nature, and hence track back to design: ‘Since biological evolution depends on stellar evolution . . . the necessity of fine-tuning for biological evolution has already been proven. Even now, Darwinism cannot claim to be designer-free.’[140] A finely tuned ‘primal soup’ suggests an intelligent ‘Primal Cook’! However, ‘The “prebiotic soup hypothesis,” popularized by Miller’s experiment, came under withering criticism from chemists for ignoring the role of competing and destructive cross-reactions. . . that would be expected in any hypothetical ocean or pond.’[141] Moreover, ‘Miller and Urey’s experiment only works as long as oxygen is absent and certain critical ratios of hydrogen and carbon dioxide are maintained.’[142] As Dean L. Overman explains: ‘The presence of even a small amount of oxygen, assiduously avoided in the laboratories of these experiments, would prevent the formation of amino acids and nucleotides. . .’[143] Of course, if oxygen were not present, the molecules of life would have been unprotected from deadly ultraviolet radiation: ‘What we have then is a sort of “Catch 22” situation. If we have oxygen we have no organic compounds, but if we don’t have oxygen we have none either.’[144] Scientists now think that oxygen was present in the early earth’s atmosphere, and that ‘the atmosphere of the early earth was mostly made up of carbon dioxide and ammonia [meaning that the Miller-Urey] experiment was not relevant to origin of life scenarios.’[145] Hurbert P. Yockey comments: ‘The “Warm little pond” scenario was invented ad hoc as a materialistic reductionist explanation of the origin of life. It is unsupported by any other evidence and it will remain ad hoc until such evidence is found.’[146]
These problems aside: ‘The information filled molecules of life are much more complex and structured than previously thought.’[147] Denyse O’Leary reports how: ‘Darwin thought that the world under the microscope consisted of simple jellies and crystals that could easily form randomly. He could not have been more wrong. It was only with the dawn of biochemistry in the 1950’s – when scientists were able to look into cells deeply and in detail – that they realized how wrong he was.’[148] Nobel Prize-winning physiologist George Beadle reports that DNA ‘was believed by many to be a rather monotonous polymer built of four kinds of nucleotide units arranged in segments of four that were repeated manifold’.[149] According to fellow Nobel winner Max Delbruck: ‘it was believed that DNA was a stupid substance.’[150] However, we now know that DNA is very far from being a monotonous polymer, but is in fact an exceedingly complex and ‘clever’ substance. The products of tightly controlled and unrealistic laboratory experiments fall far short of the complex protein molecules required for life: ‘Miller’s optimism has now all but evaporated, as experiments based on his model have failed to produce a number of components essential to life.’[151] Varghese reports: ‘Miller acknowledges today that the real problem is making polymers – like proteins – from simple chemicals like amino acids, something that still eludes experimentalists.’[152] Mark Shea remarks:
it has always struck me as odd to point to the immense concentration of intellect, will, technology and energy it has taken to do relatively small things in the extremely specialized conditions of the lab (which nature allegedly did without benefit of any of this) and argue that this product of white-hot focus of ultra-controlling human intelligence is clear evidence that absolutely no intelligence was involved in the production of the rest of the vastly more complex life we see around us. It’s like taking years to build a tiny house of cards and then using this feat to say, ‘There! This accomplishment shows the Capitol Dome was therefore obviously the product of a hurricane in a marble quarry.’[153]
As Chemist Jonathan Sarfati writes: ‘the very roots of the alleged evolutionary tree are in very bad shape’.[154]
‘Today it takes a great deal of faith to be an honest scientist who is an atheist.’ - Walter L. Bradley[155]
What is the best explanation for the amazing molecules of life? Dawkins offers the following: ‘Nobody knows how it happened but, somehow, without violating the laws of physics and chemistry, a molecule arose that just happened to have the property of self-copying – a replicator.’[156] Here, at least, is a frank admission of ignorance: ‘I would have to be more of a chemist that I am to know how likely it is that you are going to get such molecules,’ says Dawkins, ‘I don’t know how difficult it would be to achieve that chemically.’[157] Can we consider for a moment how significant and amazing it is that Professor Dawkins, who regularly accuses theists of blind faith and who exhorts people to always ask, ‘What kind of evidence is there for that?’,[158] should believe in what he calls the sine qua non of evolution without a shred of evidence?[159] As Johnson complains: ‘The naturalistic evolution of life from prebiotic chemicals and its subsequent naturalistic evolution into complexity. . . is assumed as a matter of first principle. . .’[160] Benjamin Wiker comments that Dawkins’ ‘lapse into an irrational faith in the powers of chance to avoid [intelligent design]. . . is not evidence itself but a telling lapse into a materialist credo quia absurdum est’.[161] In fact, there doesn’t appear to be anything like sufficient evidence for abiogenesis, for as Walter L. Bradley observes: ‘the origin of a sophisticated system that is both rich in information and capable of reproducing itself has absolutely stymied origin-of-life scientists’.[162]
Not only does naturalistic science lack an explanation of how life is supposed to have arrived on the cosmic scene, it actually lacks any evidence that life ‘just happened’. As G. A. Kerkut of the Department of Physiology and Biochemistry at the University of Southampton writes, it is ‘a matter of faith on the part of the biologist that biogenesis did occur. . .’[163] That abiogenesis ‘just happened’, as Dawkins’ comments make clear, is a philosophical deduction entailed by the assumption of naturalism. It is, as chemist Robert Shapiro writes: ‘mythology rather than science’.[164]
Manfred Schidlowsky argues that: ‘the very fact that life sprang up on earth constitutes conclusive proof of a primary reducing environment [i.e. one like the Miller-Urey experiment used] since the latter is a necessary prerequisite for chemical evolution and spontaneous origin of life’.[165] But as Overman comments: ‘This is a good example of. . . circular reasoning. . . in which evidence is ignored in order to maintain a myth, and the conclusion is set forth in the premise.’[166] While theists and agnostics have a healthy bias in favour of naturalistic explanations when these are adequate, they cannot treat such a circular deduction as the unquestionable and absolute certainty that it must be for Dawkins. Rather, they will be open to following the evidence.
Stephen C. Meyer calculates that: ‘the probability of constructing a rather short functional protein at random [is] so small as to be effectively zero. . .’[167] In other words, not only does naturalistic science lack an explanation of how the chemistry of life arose, or evidence to show that life ‘just happened’, it also flies in the face of evidence that life didn’t ‘just’ happen! As Thaxton, Bradley and Olsen note: ‘a slowly emerging line or boundary has appeared which shows observationally the limits of what can be expected from matter and energy left to themselves’.[168]
Dawkins, who affirms that ‘We can accept a certain amount of luck in our explanations, but not too much’[169], admits that the chance origin of life theory ‘may seem like a big stroke of luck’;[170] but he seeks to mitigate against this admission by saying: ‘it had to happen only once. . . it may have happened on only one planet out of a billion billion planets in the universe’.[171] But this is mere optimistic hand waving. The universe ‘probably contains no more than one planet for every thousand stars’,[172] and ‘it is unlikely that there are many, if any, other earth-like planets in the universe’[173] able to sustain life.
Benjamin Wiker relates some of the finely tuned conditions that permit life on earth:
Our sun is not a typical star but is one of the 9 percent most massive stars in our galaxy, and is also very stable. Further, the sun hits the Goldilocks mean for life – neither too hot (like a blue or white star) nor too cold (like a red star) – and its peak emission is right at the visible part of the electromagnetic spectrum – the very, very thin band where not only vision is possible but also photosynthesis. Earth just “happens” to have the right combination of atmospheric gases to block out almost all the harmful radiation on the electromagnetic spectrum but, strangely enough, opens like a window for visible light. Jupiter is deftly placed and sized so that it not only helps to balance the Earth’s orbit but also acts as a kind of debris magnet keeping Earth from being pummeled. Our moon is just the right size and distance to stabilize earth’s axial tilt so that we have seasonal variations but not wildly swinging temperature changes.[174]
Astronomer Hugh Ross lists 200 parameters required for a life-bearing planet. Comparing the chances of a planet falling within these parameters by chance alone with our best estimate of the total number of planets in the universe (1022) he estimates that there is ‘less than 1 chance in 10215’ of even one habitable planet existing in the universe ‘without invoking divine miracles’.[175] Elsewhere, Ross writes that: ‘fewer than a trillionth of a trillionth of a percent of all stars will have a planet capable of sustaining advanced life. Considering that the observable universe contains less than a trillion galaxies, each averaging a hundred billion stars, we can see that not even one planet would be expected, by natural processes alone, to possess the necessary conditions to sustain life.’[176] Astrobiologists Peter D. Ward and Donald Brownlee conclude that: ‘If some god-like being could be given the opportunity to plan a sequence of events with the express goal of duplicating our “Garden of Eden”, that power would face a formidable task. With the best intentions, but limited by natural laws and materials, it is unlikely that Earth could ever be truly replicated.’[177]
For another thing, according to Meyer, to generate a single functional protein of 150 amino acids exceeds: ‘1 chance in 10180, well beyond the most conservative estimates for the small probability bound. . . it is extremely unlikely that a random search through all the possible amino acid sequences could generate even a single relatively short functional protein in the time available since the beginning of the universe. . .’[178] In The Blind Watchmaker, Dawkins simply says: ‘Given enough time, anything is possible.’[179] But there simply isn’t enough time available to sustain the plausibility of abiogenesis. Professor of Mathematics at Cardiff University, Chandra Wickramasinghe, concludes: ‘Living systems could not have been generated by random processes, within a finite time-scale, in a finite universe.’[180]
Dawkins’ blithe, hand waving ignorance of the evidence against the naturalistic origin of life from non-life surely shows, as Michael Behe comments, ‘the need to treat Darwinian scenarios. . . with a hermeneutic of suspicion’.[181] Behe goes on to observe: ‘Some scientists believe so strongly in Darwinism that their critical judgments are affected, and they will unconsciously overlook pretty obvious problems with Darwinian scenarios, or confidently assert things which are objectively untrue.’[182] The evidence seems to point in quite another direction. Keith Ward takes stock of the implications of the improbabilities of life ‘just happening’: ‘It seems hugely improbable that, in the primeval seas of the planet earth, amino acids should meet and combine to form large molecular structures capable of self-replication. . . The motive for positing some sort of intelligent design is almost overwhelming.’[183]
Likewise, Hoyle and Wickramasinghe conclude:
the enormous information content of even the simplest living systems. . . cannot in our view be generated by what are often called ‘natural’ processes. . . There is no way in which we can expect to avoid the need for information, no way in which we can simply get by with a bigger and better organic soup, as we ourselves hoped might be possible. . . The correct position we think is. . . an intelligence, which designed the biochemicals and gave rise to the origin of carbonaceous life. . . This is tantamount to arguing that carbonaceous life was invented by noncarbonaceous intelligence. . .[184]
Hoyle and Wickramasinghe stop short of making the philosophical identification of their ‘noncarbonaceous intelligence’ with God, but note:
It is ironic that the scientific facts throw Darwin out, but leave William Paley, a figure of fun to the scientific world for more than a century, still in the tournament with a chance of being the ultimate winner. . . Indeed, such a theory is so obvious that one wonders why it is not widely accepted as being self-evident. The reasons are psychological rather than scientific.[185]
Dembski’s explicit formulation of the criteria for design detection used by Dawkins naturally leads us to agree with Dawkins about Mt. Rushmore being designed. However, if we apply the very same design-detection criteria to DNA, for example, we get the very same conclusion: Design. Yet philosopher Norman L. Geisler follows the evidence while Dawkins will not:
suppose I come upon a round stratisfied stone and were asked how it came to be such. I might plausibly answer that it was once laid down by water in layers which later solidified by chemical action. One day it broke from a larger section of rock and was subsequently rounded by the natural erosional processes of tumbling in water. Suppose then. . . I come upon Mount Rushmore. . . Even if I knew nothing about the origin of the faces, would I not come immediately to believe it was an intelligent production and not the result of natural processes of erosion? Yet why should a natural cause serve for the stone but not for the faces? For this reason, namely, that when we come to inspect the faces on the mountain we perceive – what we could not discover in the stone – that. . . they convey specifically complex information. . .[186]
Thus far Dawkins agrees, and for the same reasons; but he begs-the-question in order to avoid extending that agreement to Geisler’s consistent conclusion:
Suppose also that in studying the genetic structure of a living organism, we discover that its DNA has a highly complicated and unique information code, distinguished by its specified complexity. . . would we not conclude that it most probably took intelligence to produce a living organism?[187]
To substitute the terms in Dawkins’ own argument: undirected natural causes could have done the same job. But of all the possible ways of arranging amino acids, only a tiny minority would match the biological specification for functionality. Hence, even without knowing the history of DNA, we’d estimate the odds against its occurrence by natural processes as astronomically high. But if natural processes didn’t do the job, what did? Philosopher of science Stephen C. Meyer has the answer:
Our experience-based knowledge of information-flow confirms that systems with large amounts of specified complexity (especially codes and languages) invariably originate from an intelligent source. . . As Quastler (1964) put it, the ‘creation of new information is habitually associated with conscious activity.’ (p. 16). Experience teaches this obvious truth.[188]
The evidence argues for intelligent design, but Dawkins allows the philosophical dogma of naturalism to trump the evidence and shoehorn it into the naturalistically acceptable category of ‘designoid’, even though doing so requires an ad hoc redefinition of his own term that ignores his own design detection criteria.
According to Professor Richard Norman, Darwin’s core argument goes like this: Variations exist within existing populations of domesticated plants and animals. Human breeders have intelligently selected which set of characteristics get to breed, such that ‘small variations can be accumulated over many generations to produce, say, a new breed of sheep of a new variety of rose.’[189] Darwin argued that an analogous process of selection happens in nature: ‘what he calls “the struggle for existence” functions as a mechanism of selection comparable to selection and breeding by human beings.’[190]
Darwin’s analogy between intelligent and natural selection implies that a non-intelligent process is analogous to a process requiring the involvement of intelligent agents, that a process in which the offspring are exposed to harsh environmental conditions is analogous to a process in which offspring are protected from the environment, and that a process in which offspring can interbreed in the wild is analogous to a process where the breeding of offspring is carefully orchestrated. This strains credulity in itself.
Since there is ‘no clear divide’ between varieties and species, the gradual accumulation of modifications can presumably produce changes that are not just new varieties, but new species, etc. Hence, ‘continued over vast periods of time’, this process of natural selection ‘is sufficient to account for the gradual emergence of all the species of living things which have existed’.[191] As Carl Zimmer asserts: ‘If you accept microevolution, you get macroevolution for free.’[192]
To quote Professor Norman’s summary of Darwin’s argument:
The argument appears to be logically valid. Premise one is above reproach; as is premise two (in that we know changing environmental conditions can alter the proportional representation of pre-existing variations within a population of organisms). However, premise three (which really needs to go further than the level of species, and I will take this extension as read in order to avoid attacking a straw-man) is a very large and therefore inherently shaky extrapolation from premise two. As mathematician David Berlinski writes:
The most ardent creationist now accept micro-evolution as genuinely Darwinian events. They had better: such are the facts. But the grand evolutionary progressions, such as the transformation of a fish into a man, are examples of macro-evolution. They remain out of reach, accessible only at the end of an inferential trail.[194]
The further one extends an inferential trail, the less solid it becomes. Our knowledge of ‘micro-evolutionary’ changes does little to support belief in full-blown ‘macro-evolution’ (evolution beyond the level of species, and/or the evolution of new organs and body-plans). For example, after a 1977 drought in the Galapagos islands, scientists found that the surviving finches had beaks that were 4% longer and 6% deeper than the average pre-drought beak. Then, after a period of very wet conditions, scientists found that the average beak size of the surviving finches was about 1% narrower than before the drought! This is a good example of ‘micro-evolutionary’ change: ‘The change in average beak size is an example of minor variations being selected from genetic information already present in the gene pool.’[195] (Note that the change was cyclical and not in a uniform direction.) To extrapolate from such examples of minor variations within a pre-existing gene pool to the belief that ‘There is no reason why the process of natural selection which produces new varieties may not, over sufficiently long periods of time, also produce varieties so different as to constitute new species [and more]’, is rather like arguing that since an Olympic runner can cover a mile in four minutes there is no reason that he may not cover sixteen miles in sixty-four minutes! Obviously not. There are limiting factors that mean this extrapolation is unrealistic:
Think of an archer shooting an arrow. Let’s say that the arrow travels at about 150 MPH. So, in half an hour, it should be able to hit a target 75 miles away, right? Obviously, that won’t happen. There are limiting forces like friction and gravity that dramatically slow the speed of the arrow after the first 50 yards or so.[196]
Simply assuming that there are no limiting factors does not prove that there are none! There is reason to believe that evolution might account for speciation (this hypothesis is the smallest and hence most secure extrapolation from the evidence of observed micro-evolution, and there is some circumstantial evidence in its favour[197]). However, evidence for more extensive macro-evolutionary change, especially change involving the appearance of new organs and/or new body plans, is lacking. And as David DeWolf, Stephen C. Meyer and Mark E. DeForrest observe:
Evidence from developmental biology suggests clear limits to the amount of evolutionary change that organisms can undergo, [hence there is evidence of limiting factors] casting doubt on the Darwinian theory of common descent and suggesting a reason for morphological stasis in the fossil record.[198]
‘As an illustration of the fossil record, the Tree of Life is a dismal failure. But it is a good representation of Darwin’s theory.’ – Jonathan Wells[199]
The fossil record does little to endorse Darwinian gradualism, as Robert C. Koons observes:
the fossil record of the family tree of evolution is so gappy that it consists of a great deal more gap than tree. This is especially true where the record is most complete, as in the case of the invertebrates. The missing links that have been found, like the Archaeopteryx or Australopithecus, are better described as mosaics: re-combinations of adaptations found in what are assumed to be related families. Given that the forms of life found in the fossil record are more numerous and variegated than those we find alive today, it is not at all surprising that we should find fossil forms that are ‘intermediate’ in some vague sense between living forms. What we don’t find is the kind of continuous, seamless web of transformation of adaptive structures that would be needed to confirm the truth of Darwinism.[200]
Robert F. Dehaan and John L. Wiester report that: ‘each phylum is self-bounded. Indeed, there are no transitional forms between them, as predicted by Darwinian theory.’[201] David B. Kitts writes that:
Despite the bright promise that paleontology provides a means of seeing evolution, it has presented some nasty difficulties for evolutionists, the most notorious of which is the presence of ‘gaps’ in the fossil record. Evolution requires intermediate forms between species and paleontology does not provide them.[202]
Kitts concludes: ‘The gaps must therefore be a contingent feature of the record’[203], but this is to argue from the assumption of macroevolution to an ad hoc explanation for the poor fit between theory and evidence, and to accept the fact that the fossil record fails to verify Darwin’s theory. The fossil record has become something for evolutionary theory to explain away rather than something that provides positive support for macro-evolution.
Moreover, according to Luther Sunderland: ‘The gaps between major groups of organisms have been growing ever wider and more undeniable. They can no longer be ignored or rationalized away with appeals to the imperfection of the fossil record.’[204] With around 250 million catalogued fossils, representing some 250,000 species, ‘the problem does certainly not appear to be an imperfect record. Many scientists have conceded that the fossil record is sufficiently complete to provide an accurate portrait of the geologic record.’[205] For example, Niles Eldridge writes: ‘The record jumps, and all the evidence shows that the record is real: the gaps we see reflect real events in life’s history – not the artefact of a poor fossil record.’[206] University of Chicago Professor of geology David Raup says:
we are now about 120 years after Darwin and the knowledge of the fossil records has been greatly expanded. We now have a quarter of a million fossil species but the situation hasn’t changed much. The record of evolution is still surprisingly jerky and, ironically, we have even fewer examples of evolutionary transition than we had in Darwin’s time.[207]
A study published in the February 26th 1999 issue of Science indicates that ‘the fossil record is virtually complete in what it has to reveal.’[208] The study combined data analysis of hundreds of mammal fossils with a mathematical model of evolutionary branching patterns in an attempt to determine the completeness of the fossil record prior to 65 million years ago:
The researchers concluded that the fossil preservation rate is high – high enough that the probability that modern mammals existed more than 65 million years ago without leaving fossils is just .2 percent (two tenths of one percent). Study author Christine Janis, professor of ecology and evolutionary biology at Brown University, proclaimed, ‘The fossil record for that period is good enough for us to say that those species would most likely have been preserved if they had been there.’[209]
Phillip E. Johnson summarises the fossil situation:
the fossil evidence is very difficult to reconcile with the Darwinist scenario. If all living species descended from common ancestors by an accumulation of tiny steps, then there once must have existed a veritable universe of transitional intermediate forms linking the vastly different organisms of today, such as moths, trees, and humans, with their hypothetical common ancestors. From Darwin’s time to the present, palaeontologists have hoped to find the ancestors and transitional intermediates and trace the course of macroevolution. Despite claims of success in some areas, however, the results have been on the whole disappointing. That the fossil record is in important respects hostile to a Darwinist interpretation has long been known to insiders as the ‘trade secret of palaeontology.’ The secret is now coming out into the open.[210]
The fossil record not only fails to support Darwinism, it actually contradicts Darwinism. This particular Darwinian skeleton is out of the fossil cupboard! As Johnson’s comments indicate, the evidence is not uniformly inimical to macro-evolution, but even in those cases where evolutionists can claim to find evidence for macro-evolution, things are not open-and-shut. Consider Niles Eldridge’s comments, made in the context of the famous ‘horse sequence’ of fossils, where it turns out that ‘the species that were supposed to align in an evolutionary lineage actually persist unchanged and co-exist in the fossil record’[211]:
There have been an awful lot of stories, some more imaginative than others, about what the nature of that history [of life] really is. The most famous example. . . is the exhibition on horse evolution prepared perhaps fifty years ago. That has been presented as the literal truth in text-book after text-book. Now I think that this is lamentable, particularly when people who propose those kinds of stories may themselves be aware of the speculative nature of some of that stuff.[212]
Hence, while some fossil evidence might be made to fit the assumption of macroevolution, when taken as a whole, the fossil evidence can hardly be said to support turning that assumption into a conclusion.
Steve M. Stanley, professor of paleobiology at John Hopkins University, confirms that ‘The known fossil record fails to document a single example of phylitic evolution accomplishing a major morphological transition and hence offers no evidence that the gradualistic model can be valid.’[213] Gareth Nelson, a senior zoologist at the American Museum of Natural History, likewise admits that ‘evidence, or proof, of origins. . . of all the major groups of life, of all the minor groups of life, indeed of all the species – is weak or nonexistent when measured on an absolute scale.’[214] Robert Carroll observes that as our knowledge of the fossil record has increased over the past century is has only emphasised: ‘how wrong Darwin was in extrapolating the pattern of long-term evolution from that observed within populations and species.’[215] Indeed, Mark Hartwig points out that:
According to Darwinism, new phyla are produced by the gradual divergence of species. As species split off from each other over time, they eventually become so dissimilar as to constitute a whole new body plan. Therefore, we should see new species slowly appearing over time, followed by the much slower appearance of new phyla – what Harvard palaeontologist Stephen Jay Gould called a ‘cone of increasing diversity.’ Instead, the cone is upside down.[216]
Not only is Darwin’s extrapolation inherently risky given its small evidential base, the fossil record contradicts it. Nowhere is this more apparent than in the ‘Cambrian explosion’.
‘Darwinism cannot explain the Cambrian explosion. . . we need a new theory.’ – Dr. Jun-Yuan Chen, palaeontologist, Nanking Institute of Geology.[217]
The contradiction between Darwinian theory and the fossil evidence is hardly surprising when one considers the fact that: ‘empirically derived estimates of mutation rates in extant organisms suggest that the kind of large-scale morphological changes that occurred in the Cambrian would have required far more time than the duration of the explosion. . .’[218] Francis J. Beckwith reports how:
evolutionists admit that the record does not reveal gradual development from simple to more complex species, as predicted by Darwin. Rather, in what is called the ‘Cambrian explosion’ the record reveals the sudden appearance at differing times of information-rich organisms within a hierarchical diversity of species with apparently no precursors. Their body plans with their improbable arrangement of parts including the information content of their DNA. . . exhibit the characteristics of specified complexity, intelligent design. Hence, some design theorists employ the facts of the Cambrian explosion in their arguments for ID. . .[219]
For example, in a paper on ‘The Origin of Biological Information and The Higher Taxonomic Categories’, published in the Proceedings of the Biological Society of Washington (volume 117, no. 2, pp. 213-239), a peer-reviewed biology journal published at the National Museum of Natural History at the Smithsonian Institution in Washington D.C.[220], Dr. Stephen C. Meyer treats ‘the problem of the origination of the higher taxonomic groups as a manifestation of a deeper problem, namely, the problem of the origin of the information. . . necessary to generate morphological novelty.’ Meyer observes that an animal ‘form’ represents: ‘a highly specific and constrained arrangement of material components (among a much larger set of possible arrangements).’ This understanding of ‘form’ reveals a link with ‘the notion of information in its most theoretically general sense. . . producing organismal form by definition requires the generation of information.’ Applying these insights to the Cambrian explosion, Meyer notes that:
The Cambrian explosion represents a remarkable jump in the specified complexity or ‘complex specified information’ (CSI) of the biological world [because] Functionally more complex animals [as appeared in the Cambrian] require more cell types to perform their more diverse functions. New cell types require many new and specialized proteins. New proteins, in turn, require new genetic information. Thus an increase in the number of cell types implies (at minimum) a considerable increase in the amount of specified genetic information.
Studies of modern animals suggests the sponges which appeared in the late Precambrian would have required just five cell types: ‘whereas the more complex animals that appeared in the Cambrian (e.g. arthropods) would have required fifty or more cell types.’ Meyer argues that:
whether one envisions the evolutionary process beginning with a non-coding region of the genome or a pre-existing functional gene, the functional specificity and complexity of proteins impose some very stringent limitations on the efficacy of mutation and selection. In the first case, function must arise first, before natural selection can act to favor a novel variation. In the second case, function must be continuously maintained in order to prevent deleterious (or lethal) consequences to the organisms and to allow further evolution. Yet the complexity and functional specificity of proteins implies that both these conditions will be extremely difficult to meet. Therefore, the neo-Darwinian mechanism appears to be inadequate to generate the new information present in the novel genes and proteins that arise with the Cambrian animals.
Moreover:
Mutations in genes that are expressed late in the development of an organism will not affect the body plan. . . Thus, events expressed early in the development of organisms have the only realistic chance of producing large-scale macroevolutionary change. . . Yet recent studies in developmental biology make clear that mutations expressed early in development typically have deleterious effects.
This is because: ‘processes of development are tightly integrated spatially and temporally such that changes early in development will require a host of other coordinated changes in separate but functionally interrelated developmental processes downstream.’ J.F. McDonald has called this problem ‘a great Darwinian paradox’:[221]
McDonald notes that genes that are observed to vary within natural populations do not lead to major adaptive changes, while genes that could cause major changes – the very stuff of macroevolution – apparently do not vary. In other words, mutations of a kind that macroevolution doesn’t need (namely, viable genetic mutations in DNA expressed late in development) do occur, but those that it does need (namely, beneficial body plan mutations expressed early in development) apparently don’t occur. According to Darwin natural selection cannot act until favourable variations arise in a population. Yet there is no evidence from developmental genetics that the kind of variations required by neo-Darwinism – namely, favourable body plan mutations – ever occur.
Given the inadequacy of evolutionary explanations of the CSI increase represented in the Cambrian explosion, and given our every-day experience of intelligent agents as sufficient causal explanations for such increases in CSI, Meyer concludes that: ‘experience-based analysis of the causal powers of various explanatory hypotheses suggests purposive or intelligent design as a causally adequate – and perhaps the most causally adequate – explanation for the origin of the complex specified information required to build the Cambrian animals and the novel forms the represent.’
In their paper ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’[222], Meyer, Ross, Nelson and Chien observe that:
When we compare the pattern of fossilization in the actual fossil record to the expected pattern given the neo-Darwinian mechanism, we encounter significant dissonance. Neither the pace nor the mode of evolutionary change match neo-Darwinian expectations. Indeed, the neo-Darwinism mechanism cannot explain the geologically sudden origin or the major body plans to which the term ‘the Cambrian explosion’ principally refers. Further, the absence of plausible transitional organisms, the pattern of disparity preceding diversity, and the pattern of phyla first appearance all run counter to the neo-Darwinian expectations. Although. . . the newer punctuationist model of evolutionary change appears more consonant with some aspects of the Cambrian/Precambrian fossil record, it too, fails to account for the extreme absence of transitional intermediaries, the top-down pattern of diversity, and the pattern of phylum first appearance. . .[223]
They note how ‘These problems underscore a more significant theoretical difficulty for evolutionary theory generally, namely, the insufficiency of attempts to extrapolate microevolutionary mechanisms to explain macroevolutionary development’[224], and go on to argue that:
we see in the fossil record several distinctive features or hallmarks of designed systems, including: (1) a quantum or discontinuous increase in specified complexity or information; (2) a top-down pattern of innovation in which large-scale morphological disparity arises before small-scale diversity; (3) the persistence of structural (or ‘morphological’) disparities between separate organized systems; and (4) the discrete or simultaneous emergence of functionally integrated parts within novel organizational body plans. . . in other words, intelligent design constitutes the best, most causally adequate, explanation of the specific features of the Cambrian explosion. . .[225]
‘I have no theological problem with random mutation as the vehicle of evolution; it still leaves open the need for a source of nature and its laws. Similarly I have no problem with the existence of unicorns. I just find both beliefs to be equally fanciful.’ – Roy Abraham Varghese[226]
Phillip E. Johnson argues that none of the examples of microevolution: ‘provides any persuasive reason for believing that natural selection can produce new species, new organs, or other major changes. . .’[227] Darwin’s bold extrapolation from observed micro-evolutionary change to the hypothesis that macroevolution accounts for all organic variation simply assumed that there are no limiting factors analogous to the limiting factors that came into play in the story about the Olympic runner or the story about the archer; hence Professor Norman is building a house on sand when he asserts that: ‘the Darwinian explanation shows how . . . these mechanisms can account for the emergence of species [and more]’.[228] By way of contrast, biologist Keith Thompson of Oxford University says that: ‘no one has satisfactorily demonstrated a mechanism at the population genetic level by which innumerable very small. . . changes could accumulate rapidly to produce large changes: a process for the origin of the magnificently improbable from the ineffably trivial’.[229]
At best, the Darwinian explanation suggests how the observed mechanism of natural selection might account for the emergence of species (and more) if there are no limiting factors that invalidate what is at any rate a risky extrapolation from the available data. As David L. Hull of the University of Wisconsin observes: ‘The leading philosophers contemporary with Darwin, John Herchet, William Whewell, and John Stewart Mill, were equally adamant in their conviction that the Origin of Species was just one mass of conjecture.’[230] They were right. As Nancy Pearcey and Charles Colson comment: ‘It was a bold speculation, but no one should be misled into thinking it was more than that. . . It is a conjecture, an extrapolation going far beyond any observed facts.’[231]
Darwin’s ‘risky’ hypothesis (to borrow a term from philosopher of science Karl Popper) was a good scientific hypothesis that was well worth checking out, but 150 years of checking have indicated that Darwin was at best only partly right: ‘Yes, small-scale evolution is a fact’, writes molecular biophysicist Cornelius G. Hunter, ‘but there is no reason to think it is unbounded. In fact, all our data suggests that small-scale evolution cannot produce the sort of large-scale change Darwinism requires.’[232] On the basis of the fossil record, Dehaan and Wiester conclude: ‘The Darwinian mechanism of selection and variation does provide a plausible explanation for minor variations among species, such as the variations of shapes in finches’ beaks. But this mechanism plays no discernable part in the formation of major innovations’[233] As Roger Lewin stated in his summary of the Chicago ‘Macroevolution’ conference in 1980:
The central question of the Chicago conference was whether the mechanisms underlying microevolution can be extrapolated to explain the phenomena of macroevolution. At risk of doing violence to the position of some people at this meeting, the answer can be given as a clear, No.[234]
Today, Cornelius G. Hunter reports that:
if one looks in the research journals, one finds that evolutionists are unsure whether small-scale evolution could possibly account for the needed large-scale change. . . From genetics to palaeontology and other disciplines, the message is that evolution’s necessary large-scale change does not appear to be a simple case of small-scale change extrapolated over time.[235]
Hence Jonathan Well’s argues that:
common ancestry is certainly true at the species level, but is it true at higher levels? It becomes an increasingly uncertain inference the higher we go in the taxonomic hierarchy. When you get to the level of phyla, the major animal groups, it’s a very, very shaky hypothesis. In fact, I would say it’s disconfirmed. The evidence just doesn’t support it.[236]
The extrapolation from observed microevolution to an explanatorily sufficient macroevolution (based on the assumption that there are no limiting factors) is contradicted by our knowledge of mutation rates, developmental biology, and the fossil record. Macro-evolution just doesn’t seemed to have happened. As Johnson comments:
Claims that natural selection is a force of stupendous creative power, which is capable of crafting the immense complexity of biological structures that living creatures possess in such abundance, are not supported by experimental evidence or observation. . . Observational evidence (e.g. the famous peppered moth study) shows mainly cyclical changes in the relative frequency of characteristics already present in the population. There is circumstantial evidence pointing to somewhat more impressive changes (e.g. circumpolar gulls, Hawaiian fruit-fly species), but the empirical evidence gives no reason for confidence that natural selection has the creative power, regardless of the amount of time available, to build up complex organs from scratch or to change one body plan into another. . . The decisive disconfirmation of neo-Darwinism comes from the fossil record. Even if we generously grant the assumption that neo-Darwinist macroevolution is capable of producing basic changes, it does not appear to have done so.[237]
Moreover, as Ralph O. Muncaster reports: ‘The technical advances of the latter part of the twentieth century have allowed scientists to recognize the challenges to the evolutionary process at the molecular level.’[238]
According to Darwinian theory biological systems evolve through the incremental accumulation of beneficial mutations: ‘natural selection acts only by taking advantage of slight successive variations; she can never take a great a sudden leap, but must advance by short and sure, though slow steps’.[239] Dawkins explains why: ‘The larger the leap through genetic space, the lower the probability that the resulting change will be viable, let alone an improvement. [Hence] evolution must in general be a crawl through genetic space, not a series of leaps.’[240] He describes this gradual approach to obtaining biological complexity as ‘Climbing Mount Improbable’.[241] Improbable because, as Steven Vogel writes, the theory stipulates that: ‘Nature in effect must transmute a motorcycle into an automobile while providing continuous transportation. The need for growth without loss of function can impose severe geometrical limitations.’[242] As Stephen Jay Gould admitted: ‘Our inability, even in our imagination, to construct functional intermediaries in many cases has been a persistent and nagging problem for gradualistic accounts of evolution.’[243] Gould also pointed out that: ‘The fossil record with its abrupt transitions offers no support for gradual change. . . palaeontologists know that the fossil record contains precious little in the way of intermediate forms; transitions between major groups are characteristically abrupt.’[244] Nevertheless, naturalists, who assume that evolution is true because it fills the explanatory gap left by the exclusion of design, have been content to say that even though we have no idea what path organisms took up Mount Improbable, they must have done so.
For example, Dawkins says that: ‘however daunting the sheer cliffs that the adaptive mountain first presents, graded ramps can be found the other side and the peak eventually scaled’.[245] How does he know that these ‘graded ramps can be found’ in advance of showing what they are; without even looking for them? Because his justification for this assumption is philosophical rather than scientific: ‘Without stirring from our chair, we can see that it must be so’,[246] explains Dawkins, ‘because nothing except gradual accumulation could, in principle, do the job. . .’[247] What job is that? The job of explaining life naturalistically! As Daniel Dennet admits: ‘This is a purely theory-driven explanation, argued a-priori from the assumption that natural selection tells the true story – some true story or other – about every curious feature of the biosphere. . . it assumes that Darwinism is basically on the right track.’[248] Once again, Dawkins’ conclusion rests upon his presupposition that there is no designer: ‘this sort of argument smacks of tautology’, complains Michael Denton: ‘The only warrant for believing that functional living systems are. . . capable of undergoing functional transformation by random mechanisms, is belief in evolution by the natural selection of purely random changes in the structure of living things. But this is precisely the question at issue.’[249]
Absence of evidence for precise causal histories of how Mount Improbable was supposedly conquered by gradualistic means is not conclusive evidence of an absence of such ascents (although the burden of proof is on the hypothesis that such events happened); but while design theorists are biased in favour of naturalistic explanations where they are adequate, the improbability of the gradualistic hypothesis, together with its pervasive lack of evidential support, counts against it as an explanation for anything that looks designed (at least for anyone without a dogmatic commitment to design-free explanations). As Dembski explains:
Darwinism is committed to a sequence of manageable steps that gradually transforms A into B. In consequence, there has to be some sequence. . . where each transition from one step to the next can readily be accounted for in terms of natural selection and random variation. Thus, for instance, in a Darwinian explanation of the bacterial flagellum, we know that bacteria lacking a flagellum (and also lacking any genes coding for a flagellum) had to evolve into bacteria with a flagellum (and thus possessing a novel genetic complement for the flagellum). If Darwinism is correct, some step-by-step Darwinian process had to take us from the former type of bacteria to the latter. So how did it happen? How could it have happened? Nature somehow filled in the details, but Darwinists somehow never do.[250]
Dawkins reports ‘feeling. . . that provided the difference between neighbouring intermediates in our series [of forms] is sufficiently small, the necessary mutations are almost bound to be forthcoming’.[251] However, we know that: ‘The DNA replication process for higher organisms includes proofreading to keep error rates at less than one in ten billion [while] errors that do occur are almost invariably neutral or harmful.’[252]
For example, Darwinists have failed to provide evidence that the eye could be evolved from scratch though any series of ‘sufficiently small’ mutations, let alone to provide evidence that any eye historically followed any such evolutionary pathway: ‘Ingenious hypothetical scenarios for the evolution of complex adaptations are presented to the public virtually as fact, but sceptics within science derisively call them “just-so” stories, because they can be neither tested experimentally nor supported by fossil histories.’[253] Biologist Michael Denton notes that: ‘through what intermediate states the reflecting eye evolved is a mystery’.[254] Indeed, cell biologist Franklin Harold admits: ‘There are presently no detailed Darwinian accounts of the evolution of any biochemical or cellular system, only a variety of wishful speculations.’[255] Even the just-so stories tend to ‘artificially isolate a particular component or organ, such as the eye, from the immensely complex system [i.e. the organism] in which it is embedded’.[256] As Johnson complains: ‘There is no requirement that any of this speculation be confirmed by either experimental or fossil evidence. For Darwinists, just being able to imagine the process is sufficient to confirm that something like that must have happened.’[257]
Dawkins argues that different forms of eye present in nature can be arranged into a sequence from less to more complex, and that this sequence shows the viability of a Darwinian explanation of the eye: ‘modern analogues of every step up the ramp can be found, working serviceably in dozens of eyes dotted independently around the animal kingdom’.[258] However, not only is this sequence of eyes historically hypothetical (showing at best what could rather than what did happen), but its supposedly simple beginning actually assumes the existence of ‘a cell sensitive to light and able to react in a specific way to visible radiation. . .’[259] That light sensitive cell, far from being simple, is an example of an ‘irreducibly complex’ (IC) system that can’t have evolved directly by incremental modifications of a precursor system, because all of its parts are necessary to its performing its function. As Jakob Wolf complains: ‘far from commanding the resources to explain their emergence, Darwinian explanation consistently presupposes the existence of irreducibly complex systems’.[260] Hence recent discoveries in microbiology mean that the pervasive absence of evidence for the climbing of ‘Mount Improbable’ has now been transmuted into evidence of absence:
Climbing Mount Improbable requires taking a slow serpentine route up the backside of the mountain and avoiding precipices. For irreducibly complex systems that have numerous diverse parts and that exhibit the minimal level of complexity needed to retain a minimal level of function, such a gradual ascent up Mount Improbable is no longer possible.[261]
For some biological systems (systems exhibiting IC), the task of climbing ‘Mount Improbable’ is to all intents and purposes the task of climbing Mount Impossible. If a biological system exhibits irreducible complexity, then evolution by natural selection is in serious trouble as an adequate explanatory hypothesis (and intelligence, as the only cause known to be capable of originating irreducibly complexity, moves to the fore as the best explanation of IC systems).
Darwin argued that the existence of a single irreducibly complex system would falsify his evolutionary hypothesis: ‘If it could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed which could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive modifications, my theory would absolutely break down.’[262] Darwin was betting that no such system would be discovered.
Richard Dawkins places the same bet when he acknowledges that Darwin’s remark ‘is valid and very wise. . . his theory is indeed falsifiable. . . and he puts his finger on one way in which it might be falsified’.[263] However, he asserts that ‘not a single case is known to me of a complex organ that could not have been formed by numerous slight [un-guided] modifications. I do not believe that such a case will ever be found.’[264] Nevertheless, he concedes: ‘If it is – it’ll have to be a really complex organ, and . . . you have to be sophisticated about what you mean by “slight” – I shall cease to believe in Darwinism.’[265] Like Darwin, Dawkins has a lot riding on the universal negative bet that nothing in nature is irreducibly complex.
Massimo Pigliucci goes further than Darwin and Dawkins, writing that: ‘irreducible complexity is indeed a hallmark of intelligent design.’[266] If there is irreducible complexity in living organisms, then Pigliucci would accept this as evidence of intelligent design: ‘irreducible complexity is indeed a valid criterion to distinguish between intelligent and nonintelligent design.’[267] However, like Darwin and Dawkins, Pigliucci thinks that: ‘there is no evidence so far of irreducible complexity in living organisms.’[268] Note that the issue here is a dispute about evidence, about the empirically knowable facts of the matter – it is, in that sense, a scientific dispute.
‘Behe . . . does have a point concerning irreducible complexity. . .’ – Massimo Pigliucci[269]
The concept of irreducible complexity is not new. Nor are design arguments based upon the concept. Popular summaries of William Paley notwithstanding, his argument goes well beyond analogy, however impressive. Although he didn’t employ this precise terminology, Paley pointed out that a watch is, at its core, irreducibly complex. That is, not only is the watch’s purpose carried out by the sum of the watch’s parts, but that purpose could not be carried out ‘if its different parts had been differently shaped from what they are, or placed after any other manner or in any other order than that in which they are placed . . .’[270] In the contemporary literature of design, a system performing a given basic function (like a watch telling the time), is said to be ‘irreducibly complex’ if it includes a set of well-matched, mutually interacting, non-arbitrarily individuated parts such that each part in the set is indispensable to maintaining the system’s basic function. The set of indispensable parts is the irreducible core of the system in question.[271] ‘The power of the concept of irreducible complexity’, writes John A. Smart, ‘is that it invalidates the step-by-step process of evolution.’[272] As Behe, Dembski and Meyer explain: ‘Natural selection can only act on systems that perform functions that help organisms survive. But “irreducibly complex” systems have no function at all unless all the parts in the system are present. Yet without the aid of natural selection the odds against such systems arising on their own are prohibitive.’[273]
The existence of an irreducibly complex system in nature is indicative of design. As atheist Daniel Dennet, who called such systems ‘the You-Couldn’t-Get-Here-From-There Organ or Organism,’[274] explains: ‘If there are designs that cannot be approached by a gradual, stepwise redesign process in which each step is at least no worse for the gene’s survival chances than its predecessor, then the existence of such a design in nature would seem to require, at some point in its ancestry, a helping hand from a foresighful designer . . .’[275] In 1945 British philosopher A.E. Taylor argued that what made an inference to design irresistible in the case of a watch was: ‘the way in which the various parts of the watch are co-adapted to produce a unitary result, and a result which cannot be effected until they are all assembled in a definite way.’[276] Taylor argued that ‘the thorough-going co-adaptation of the parts of organisms to contribute to a unitary result which will only emerge when the organism is mature may be ascribed to “prospective contrivance” with an even higher degree of probability.’[277]
University biochemist Michael J. Behe has put new life into the concept of irreducible complexity by applying the argument at the bio-molecular level of cellular machinery unknown even in Taylor’s generation. Behe’s most notable presentation of irreducible complexity is Darwin’s Black Box: the Biochemical Challenge to Evolution (1996), where he defined his terms as follows:
By irreducibly complex I mean a single system composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to basic function, wherein the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning. An irreducibly complex system cannot be produced directly . . . by slight, successive modifications of a precursor system, because any precursor to an irreducibly complex system that is missing a part is by definition non-functional.[278]
Mike Gene reports that: ‘Behe’s concept of irreducible complexity (IC) has found itself in the peer-reviewed scientific literature. . . and is being taken seriously by scientists.’[279]
By definition, any system that is irreducibly complex cannot have evolved directly up any ‘graded ramp’ round the back of ‘Mount Improbable’. Ruling out direct, incremental evolution does not exclude what Darwin called ‘a sudden leap’,[280] but as Dawkins notes: ‘The larger the leap through genetic space, the lower the probability that the resulting change will be viable, let alone an improvement.’[281] Behe observes:
Even if a system is irreducibly complex (and thus cannot have been produced directly). . . one can not definitely rule out the possibility of an indirect, circuitous route. As the complexity of an interacting system increases, though, the likelihood of such an indirect route drops precipitously. And as the number of unexplained, irreducibly complex biological systems increases, our confidence that Darwin’s criterion of failure has been met skyrockets. . .[282]
Sceptics of Behe’s hypothesis ideally need to demonstrate the existence of indirect, ‘circuitous’, graded evolutionary pathways with the following features: they achieve the gradual assembly of all and only the components required by a given IC system (in the correct, functionally specific arrangement) through a sufficiently probable series of evolutionary steps, wherein each and every step a) has a function, b) either increases the fitness of the preceding functional step or results in a system with a different advantageous function, and where c) all of these functional steps are (by definition) different to the function exhibited by the IC end-product being explained. But as Dembski observes:
The fact is that for irreducibly complex biochemical systems, no indirect Darwinian pathways are known. . . What’s needed is a seamless Darwinian account that’s both detailed and testable of how subsystems undergoing co-evolution could gradually transform into an irreducibly complex system. No such accounts are available or forthcoming. . . The absence here is pervasive and systemic. . .[283]
Critics charge Behe’s argument with failing to acknowledge that ‘absence of evidence is not evidence of absence’, but this truism has its limitations. Failing to find car one’s keys in the house doesn’t indicate they don’t exist: after all, they might be in the car and you know you own keys to be discovered. On the other hand, suppose one wasn’t sure that keys existed to be discovered, and had conducted a thorough search anyway, and had come up empty handed. The latter analogy is closer to the scientific reality of explaining IC systems. As Dembski observes:
If after repeated attempts looking in all the most promising places you don’t find what you expect to find and if you never had any evidence that the thing you were looking for existed in the first place, then you have reason to think that the thing you are looking for doesn’t exist at all. . . the absence of scientific evidence here is as complete as it is for leprechauns.[284]
Moreover, as Robert C. Koons argues, the burden of proof here: ‘is on Darwin and his defenders to demonstrate that it is really possible for at least some of the complex organs we find in nature to be formed in this way: that is, by some specific, fully articulated series of slight modifications.’[285] Darwin was right to note that demonstrating the existence of a single biological system that could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive modifications, would cause his theory to ‘absolutely break down.’[286] However, he was wrong to set the evidential bar quite so high (demonstrating the existence of a system that is highly unlikely to have been formed by numerous, successive - and unguided - modifications would cause a sufficiently catastrophic break down in his theory); and he was doubly wrong to suggest that the evolutionary hypothesis should be extended the presumption of truth until such a demonstration could be made:
the inference from complex, interdependent functionality to intelligent agency is the natural, default position. Darwinian biologists and their pupils overlook this fact at their own cognitive peril. . . The bare possibility that a non-teleological explanation of apparent design might exist is not by itself sufficient to warrant real doubt about the reality of design, any more than the bare possibility that you and I are brains in a Matrix-like vat is sufficient to warrant scepticism about the deliverances of our five senses.[287]
As Koons writes elsewhere:
The burden is on the skeptic to provide good rational or empirical grounds for believing that the false appearance of design is not unlikely under actual conditions. Design sceptics, in common with other sceptics from antiquity to the modern day, attempt an illegitimate shift in the burden of proof. The skeptic attempts to rebut a successful design inference by merely raising the possibility that the appearance of design may be illusory, challenging the defender of the inference to prove a negative – to prove that the sceptical scenarios could not have happened. The appropriate response to such sceptical challenges is to place the burden of proof where it belongs: the skeptic must provide substantial and specific grounds for doubting the soundness of the design inference in the particular case in question.[288]
Nevertheless, Behe graciously shoulders the burden of proof that should rightfully apply to the Darwinian, and argues that at the biomolecular level of life (which was an unknown ‘Black Box’ in Darwin’s day) there are several irreducibly complex molecular systems that are highly unlikely to have been formed by numerous, successive (and unguided) modifications: ‘including aspects of protein transport, blood clotting, closed circular DNA, electron transport, the bacterial flagellum, telomeres, photosynthesis, transcription regulation, and much more’.[289]
Given that such systems are resistant to naturalistic explanations, and given our everyday experience that intelligent agents regularly produce irreducibly complex systems, Behe goes on to argue that the best explanation of such molecular machines is intelligent design:
When is it reasonable to conclude, in the absence of firsthand knowledge or eyewitness accounts, that something has been designed? For discrete physical systems – if there is not a gradual route to their production – design is evident when a number of separate, interacting components are ordered in such a way as to accomplish a function beyond the individual components. The greater the specificity of the interacting components required to produce the function, the greater is our confidence in the conclusion of design.[290]
Consider just one example of an IC system discussed by Behe:
[cf. E. Coli swimming with flagella @
www.mtmi.vu.lt/pfk/funkc_dariniai/nanostructures/bacteria.htm]
In 1973 the startling, unexpected discovery was made that some bacteria swim using an outboard motor, spinning their ‘flagella’ at up to 100,000 rpm like a screw propeller: ‘The rotary motor, with a diameter of only 30 to 40 nm [nanometers], drives the rotation of The Bacterial Flagellum the flagellum at around 300 Hz, at a power level of 10-16 W with energy conversion efficiency close to 100%.’[291]
(Labelled Illustration of bacterial flagellum from ARN Molecular Museum)
The bacterial flagellum is irreducibly complex: ‘The flagellum includes an acid powered rotary engine, a stator, O-rings, bushings and a drive shaft. The intricate machinery of this molecular motor requires approximately [forty] proteins. Yet the absence of any one of these proteins results in the complete loss of motor function.’[292] One can see that a rotary motor without a propeller, or a drive shaft, or a motor, just won’t work: ‘Because the bacterial flagellum is necessarily composed of at least three parts – a paddle, a rotor, and a motor – it is irreducibly complex.’[293] Robert Macnab comments:
one can only marvel at the intricacy, in a simple bacterium, of the total motor and sensory system which has been the subject of this review and remark that our concept of evolution by selective advantage must surely be an oversimplification. What advantage could derive, for example, from a ‘preflagellum’ (meaning a subset of its components), and yet what is the probability of ‘simultaneous’ development of the organelle at a level where it becomes advantageous?[294]
Experiments have confirmed that eliminating any of the proteins that form the flagellum results in a non-functioning machine. That is, the flagellum is irreducibly complex, a fact that rules out explanation by direct evolutionary pathways and leaves the Darwinist to fall back on far chancier indirect explanations.
‘I have learned from my own embarrassing experience how easy it is to concoct remarkably persuasive Darwinian explanations that evaporate on closer inspection.’ – Daniel Dennet[296]
Christian biologist Ken Miller has argued for an indirect explanation in the case of the flagellum by pointing to the existence of the type III secretory system (TTSS),[297] which is coded for by about ten genes, each of which is structurally similar (homologous) to genes in the bacterial flagellum. Miller sees the TTSS as a functional evolutionary precursor of the flagellum capable of being selected for on its own functional merits and then augmented to produce the flagellum. However, as Dembski points out: ‘At best the TTSS represents one possible step in the indirect Darwinian evolution of the bacterial flagellum. What’s needed is a complete evolutionary path and not merely a possible oasis along the way. To claim otherwise is like saying we can travel by foot from Los Angeles to Tokyo because we’ve discovered the Hawaiian Islands.’[298] Two final points nail shut the coffin of Miller’s TTSS scenario. The first is that ‘The type III system itself is [IC], perhaps with ten IC components.’[299] The second is that: ‘The best current molecular evidence. . . points to the TTSS evolving from the flagellum and not vice versa.’[300]
H. Allen Orr (a critic of Behe) argues:
First, it will do no good to suggest that all the required parts of some biochemical pathway popped up simultaneously by mutation. Although this ‘solution’ yields a functioning system in one fell swoop, it’s so hopelessly unlikely that no Darwinian takes it seriously. . . Second, we might think that some of the parts of an irreducibly complex system evolved step by step for other purposes and were then recruited wholesale to a new function. But this is also unlikely.[301]
Nevertheless, the current favourite among indirect explanations being advanced for IC systems is Orr’s second option of the wholesale co-option of parts evolved for other functions, an option R. H. Thornhill and D. W. Ussery call ‘adoption from a different function’.[302] While the TTSS, for example, contains around ten proteins that are homologous to proteins in the flagellum, the flagellum has another thirty or so proteins, which are unique to it. As Scott Minnich, Professor of Biology at the University of Idaho, and an expert on the flagellum, says in response to the co-option hypothesis:
With a bacterial flagellum, you’re talking about a machine that’s got forty structural parts. Yes, we find ten of them are involved in another molecular machine, but the other thirty are unique. So where are you going to borrow them from? Eventually you’re going to have to account for the function of every single part as if originally having some other purpose. I mean you can only follow the argument so far, until you run into the problem that you’re borrowing from nothing. . .’[303]
Stripping away a third of the improbability Dembski calculates for the spontaneous formation of the flagellum (10-1170) doesn’t appreciably improve matters for a naturalistic explanation: ‘Applied to those remaining two-thirds of flagellar proteins, my calculation yields something like 10-780, which also falls well below my universal probability bound.’[304] As Mike Gene warns: ‘The brilliance of Darwin was to minimize the role of chance in apparent design. But once we turn to the co-option explanation, we leave this explanatory appeal behind, as chance reasserts itself into a place of prominence.’[305]
Taking what Joshua A. Smart calls ‘a Concessionary approach’[306], Dembski supposes, purely for the sake of argument, that we discover several molecular systems ‘like the TTSS that jointly took into account all the flagellar proteins’.[307] Those proteins would be ‘similar but, in all likelihood, not identical to the flagellar proteins (strict identity would itself be vastly improbable)’.[308] Such a hypothetical situation, designed to maximize the chances of an indirect explanation by co-option, ‘raises the question how those several molecular machines can come together so that proteins from one molecular machine adopt proteins from another molecular machine to form an integrated functional system like the flagellum’.[309] As Minnich says: ‘even if you concede that you have all the parts necessary to build one of these machines, that’s only part of the problem. Maybe even more complex is the assembly instructions.’[310] Dr John Bracht, managing editor of the journal Progress in Complexity, Information and Design,[311] explains:
biological functionality is turning out to be much more highly specified and precise than we had originally envisioned. . . biology is really a science of engineering, where the constraints for bio-functionality are extreme – to the point that nearly every molecular interaction is remarkably precise and tightly controlled. Molecular biology is much like a jigsaw puzzle where each piece must be specifically shaped to fit with the other pieces around it. . .[312]
Applying these observations to the proposed construction of the flagellum by co-option, Bracht writes:
The problem is that the proteins which are to become the flagellum are coming from systems that are distinctly non-flagellar in nature. . . and being co-modified from their original molecular interactions into an entirely new set of molecular interactions. Old interfaces and binding sites must be removed and new ones must be created. But given the sheer number of flagellar proteins that must co-evolve. . . the Darwinian explanation is [very unlikely and therefore] really no different from appealing to a miracle.[313]
Dembski adds the observation that: ‘the only evidence we have of successful co-option comes from engineering and confirms that intelligence is indispensable in explaining complex structures like. . . the bacterial flagellum,’[314] and he concludes: ‘We can do the probabilistic analysis at the level of individual proteins. . . Or we can do it at higher levels of organization like functional subsystems [like TTSS]. . . But all such probabilistic analyses still point up vast improbabilities.’[315]
In ‘Irreducible Complexity Revisited’, a paper reviewing the status of Behe’s concept of irreducible complexity eight years on from the publication of Darwin’s Black Box, William A. Dembski suggests that ‘the problem he has raised is, if anything, still more vexing for Darwinism that when he first raised it.’ Dembski observes that: ‘even when the most generous allowance of legitimate advantages, the probabilities computed for the Darwinian mechanism to evolve irreducibly complex biochemical systems like the bacterial flagellum always end up being exceedingly small.’[316] He goes on to explain why this is the case, arguing that the reason these probabilities always end up being so small: ‘is the difficulty of coordinating successive evolutionary changes apart from teleology. . . In attempting to coordinate the successive evolutionary changes needed to bring about irreducibly complex biomechanical machines, the Darwinian mechanism therefore encounters a number of daunting probabilistic hurdles.’[317] These hurdles include:
Dembski uses an analogy to explain what is at stake in overcoming these probabilistic hurdles. A building contractor building a house needs to overcome each of the hurdles listed above. A building contractor doesn’t find this task insurmountable. That’s because, as an intelligent agent, they have the know-how to think ahead and to coordinate all the tasks needed to clear these hurdles with reference to achieving the goal of building a house:
But the Darwinian mechanism of random variation and natural selection has none of this know-how. All it knows is how to randomly modify things and then preserve those random modifications that happen to be useful at the moment. The Darwinian mechanism is an instant gratification machine. If the Darwinian mechanism were a building contractor, it might put up a wall because of its immediate benefit in keeping out intruders from the construction site even though by building the wall now, no foundation could be laid later and, in consequence, no usable house could ever be built at all. That’s how the Darwinian mechanism works, and that’s why it is so limited.[318]
Is the limited know-how of the Darwinian mechanism adequate for the task of coordinating the biochemical events needed to clear all these hurdles? ‘To answer yes to this question,’ says Dembski, ‘is to attribute creative powers to the Darwinian mechanism that are implausible in the extreme.’[319] Considering each of the hurdles in turn gives a good idea of just how implausible:
To clear this hurdle, the Darwinian mechanism needs to be able to form novel proteins from scratch. . . the Darwinian mechanism is capable of tinkering with existing proteins or recruiting them wholesale for new uses. But there is no evidence that it can produce complex specified proteins from scratch. . . recent work on the extreme functional sensitivity of proteins provides strong evidence that certain classes of proteins are in principle un-evolveable by gradual means (and thus a fortiori by the Darwinian mechanism) because small perturbations of these proteins destroy all conceivable biological function (and not merely existing biological function). Thus, it is highly implausible that the Darwinian mechanism can generate the novel proteins. . . required in the evolution of the bacterial flagellum.[320]
Some hurdles are easier for the Darwinian mechanism to clear than others, and this is perhaps one of them. . . The only hitch could be that an item that hitherto has served a biologically useful function and is needed in the future evolution of some irreducibly complex system loses its functional advantage somewhere in the middle of the evolutionary process and thus falls into disuse. If that happens, natural selection will tend to eliminate that item, thereby rendering it unavailable.[321]
The localization hurdle. . . seems considerably more difficult for the Darwinian mechanism to clear. . . items originally assigned to certain systems need to be reassigned and recruited for use in a newly emerging system. . . But how likely is it that these items break free and get positioned at the construction site of an existing system, thereby transforming it into a newly emerging system with a novel or enhanced function? Our best evidence suggests that this repositioning of items previously assigned to different systems is improbable and becomes increasingly improbable as more items need to be repositioned simultaneously at the same location.[322]
by welcoming items that could help in the evolution of the bacterial flagellum, the construction site would also welcome items that could hinder its evolution. It follows that to the degree that the localization hurdle is easy to clear, to that degree the interfering cross-reaction hurdle is difficult to clear, and vice versa.[323] (Hurdles 3 & 4 constitute a ‘Catch 22’ situation for evolution.)
With the interface-compatibility hurdle, we come to the gravest difficulty confronting the Darwinian mechanism. . . if these items [used in constructing bio-molecular systems] were built according to common standards or conventions, there might be some reason to think that they could work together effectively. But natural selection is incapable of instituting such standards or conventions. . . In fact, common standards and conventions that facilitate the interface compatibility of distinct functional systems points not just to the design of the systems but also to a common design responsible for the common standards and conventions. . . As an instant gratification mechanism [the Darwinian mechanism] has no stake in ensuring that such structures also adhere to standards and conventions that will allow them to interface effectively with other structures down the line. . . there is no evidence, whether theoretical or experimental, that the Darwinian mechanism can clear the interface compatibility hurdle.[324]
For a Darwinian mechanism to clear the order-of-assembly hurdle is also a stretch. . . in the evolution of [IC] systems. . . we can expect the order of assembly of parts to undergo substantial permutations. . . How, then, does the order of assembly undergo the right permutations? For most biological systems, the order of assembly is entrenched and does not permit substantial deviations. The burden of evidence is therefore on the Darwinist to show that for an evolving system, the Darwinian mechanism coordinates not only the emergence of the right parts but also their assembly in the right order. Darwinists have done nothing like this.[325]
Dembski notes that it is possible to assess objectively and quantitatively the challenge that these hurdles pose to the Darwinian mechanism. Associated with each hurdle is a probability P [i.e. Pavail, Psynch, Plocal, Pi-c-r, Pi-f-c, Po-o-a]. Each of these probabilities is conditional on the proceeding ones. For example, the synchronization probability (Psynch) assesses the probability of synchronization on condition that the needed parts are available (Pavail). Consequently, the probability of an IC system arising by Darwinian means cannot exceed the following product:
Pavail x Psynch x Plocal x Pi-c-r x Pi-f-c x Po-o-a
If we define Porigin as the probability of an IC system originating by Darwinian means (the origination probability), ‘then the following inequality holds (the origination inequality)’[326]:
Porigin < Pavail x Psynch x Plocal x Pi-c-r x Pi-f-c x Po-o-a
(That is, the origination probability is equal to or less than the product.) This inequality tells us that: ‘even if one of the probabilities to the right of the inequality sign is small, then the origination probability must itself be small (indeed, no bigger than any of the probabilities on the right).’[327] We needn’t calculate all the probabilities to the right of the inequality sign to ensure that Porigin is small:
It is enough to have reliable upper bounds on these probabilities. If any one of these upper bounds is small, then so is the associated probability and so is the origination probability. And it the origination probability is small, then the irreducibly complex system in question is both highly improbably and specified (all these irreducibly complex systems are specified in virtue of their biological function). It follows that if the origination probability is small, then the system in question exhibits specified complexity; and since specified complexity is a reliable empirical marker of actual design, it follows that the system itself is designed.[328]
Hence irreducible complexity is revealed to be a concrete example of specified complexity:
The irreducibly complex systems Behe considers require numerous components specifically adapted to each other and each necessary for function. On any formal complexity-theoretic analysis, they are complex in the sense required by the complexity-specification criterion. Moreover, in virtue of their function, these systems embody patterns independent of the actual living systems. Hence these systems are also specified in the sense required by the complexity-specification criterion.[329]
Dembski summarises the argument for design from IC systems:
irreducible complexity renders biological structures provably inaccessible to direct Darwinian pathways. . . the failure of evolutionary biology to discover indirect Darwinian pathways is pervasive and systemic and therefore reason to doubt. . . that indirect Darwinian pathways are the answer to irreducible complexity. . . it’s not just that certain biological systems are so complex that we can’t imagine how they evolved by Darwinian pathways. Rather, we can show conclusively that direct Darwinian pathways are causally inadequate to bring them about and that indirect Darwinian pathways [which seem unlikely on both theoretical and experimental grounds and] are utterly without empirical support in bringing them about [and so fail to meet the proper burden of proof]. Conversely, we do know what has the causal power to produce irreducible complexity – intelligent design.[330]
Intelligent design looks like the best – most causally adequate – explanation for IC systems such as the flagellum, and Darwinists appears to be betting in the face of some long odds: ‘Like compulsive gamblers who are constantly hoping that some really big score will cancel their debts, evolutionary biologists live on promissory notes that show no sign of being redeemable. . .’[331] If biologists can meet the burden of proof by discovering or constructing detailed, testable, indirect Darwinian pathways of sufficiently high probability that account for the emergence of irreducibly and minimally complex biological systems like the bacterial flagellum, ‘then more power to them’,[332] says Dembski (the assertion that a given system is IC is scientifically falsifiable): ‘But until that happens, evolutionary biologists who claim that natural selection accounts for the emergence of the bacterial flagellum are worthy of no more credence than compulsive gamblers who are forever promising to settle their accounts.’[333]
IC systems like the bacterial flagellum are in principle inaccessible to direct Darwinian pathways, and evolutionary biologists therefore pin their hopes on the possibility that sufficiently probable indirect Darwinian pathways might one day be found to account for them. (To the best of our knowledge the odds do not favour such explanations, and hence the best explanation of such systems is intelligent design.) However, recent research points to the existence of complex biological systems that are not only inaccessible in principle to direct Darwinian pathways (making them ‘minimally’ IC), but inaccessible in principle to indirect pathways as well (making them ‘strongly’ or ‘maximally’ IC). As Dembski explains:
there is now mounting evidence of biological systems for which any slight modification does not merely destroy the system’s existing function but also destroys the possibility of any function of the system whatsoever. (Consult, for instance, the research on extreme functional sensitivity of various enzymes and on irreducibly complex metabolic pathways of enzymes for which each enzyme needs to attain a certain catalytic threshold before it or its associated pathway can serve any biological function at all.) For such systems, neither direct nor indirect Darwinian pathways could account for them.[334]
Behe’s remark that ‘if a system is irreducibly complex (and thus cannot have been produced directly). . . one can not definitely rule out the possibility of an indirect, circuitous route’[335] applies to ‘minimally irreducibly complex’ systems, but not to ‘maximally irreducibly complex’ systems. When it comes to a maximally IC system (and that includes otherwise minimally IC systems that depend upon any maximally IC systems), anyone suggesting that Darwinian mechanisms alone can offer a sufficient explanation would not only be betting against the odds, but against an in principle argument to the contrary. As Dembski observes: ‘no Darwinian account could in principle be given for the emergence of such systems’.[336]
The existence of irreducibly complex bio-molecular systems, systems that are highly unlikely to have been formed by numerous, successive, unguided modifications, causes Darwin’s extrapolation from micro to macro-evolution to ‘absolutely break down’[337] because they demonstrate the falsity of his assumption that there are no limiting factors preventing the mechanism of natural selection from explaining the full panoply of biological diversity as well as observed micro-evolutionary adjustments. Explaining IC systems by reference intelligent design, on the other hand, constitutes a causally adequate explanation that is both intuitively obvious (having the presumption of truth on its side) and is supported by design-detection criteria accepted by theists (e.g. Dembski) and atheists (e.g. Dawkins, Pigliucci) alike.
Dawkins dismisses ID theorists as: ‘a well-organised and well-financed group of nutters’.[338] But this sort of bluster (a debating tactic called ‘Poisoning the well’) should not intimidate us. Dawkins’ bark is worse than his bite (just as his philosophical skills are worse than his rhetorical skills). The fact of the matter is that ‘the epistemic status of evolutionary biology is, to say the least, a highly controversial topic’[339] and ‘a growing number of highly educated scientists. . . are becoming increasingly sceptical of evolutionary theory.’[340] Thomas Dubay reports: ‘The movement in the mainline scientific community to see design in the visible universe, and most particularly in cellular biology, is growing in strength, while its opponents have nothing but feeble and unpersuasive responses.’[341] Professor Frederick Crews grudgingly acknowledges that: ‘Intelligent design is thriving in cultural circles where illogic and self-indulgence are usually condemned.’[342]
Dembski counters Dawkins’ ad hominem attack: ‘one can be reasonably well-adjusted, remarkably well-educated (as many design theorists are), and still think Darwinism is a failed scientific paradigm.’[343] Dembski himself has a B.A in psychology, an M.S in statistics, a PhD in the philosophy of science and a PhD in mathematics (all from the University of Chicago), as well as a Master of Divinity from Princeton Theological Seminary; and he is associate research professor in the conceptual foundations of science at Baylor University. According to Dembski:
The following problems have proven utterly intractable not only for the mutation-selection mechanism but also for any other undirected natural process proposed to date: the origin of life, the origin of the genetic code, the origin of multicellular life, the origin of sexuality[344], the scarcity of transitional forms in the fossil record[345], the biological big bang that occurred in the Cambrian era[346], the development of complex organ systems and the development of irreducibly complex molecular machines. These are just a few of the more serious difficulties that confront every theory of evolution that posits only undirected natural processes. It is thus sheer arrogance for Darwinists like Richard Dawkins. . . to charge design theorists with being ignorant or stupid or wicked or insane for denying the all-sufficiency of undirected natural processes in biology. . .[347]
Dembski is alluding to a book review by Dawkins in which he affirms: ‘It is absolutely safe to say that if you meet somebody who claims not to believe in evolution, that person is ignorant, stupid or insane (or wicked, but I’d rather not consider that).’[348] Dawkins distinguishes between natural selection (‘the mutation-selection mechanism’) as Darwin’s proposed engine of evolution (about which he admits: ‘It is still (just) possible for a biologist to doubt its importance, and a few claim to.’[349]) on the one hand, and ‘the fact of evolution itself, a fact that is proved utterly beyond reasonable doubt’,[350] on the other. Hence, by ‘the fact of evolution itself’ Dawkins appears to mean the multi-faceted belief that life arose millions of years ago due only to (undirected) natural processes and then diversified from a common ancestor over millions of years merely by the operation of (undirected) natural processes. Elsewhere Dawkins circumspectly writes:
We can now assert with confidence that the theory that the Earth moves round the Sun not only is right for our time but will be right in all future times even if flat-Earthism happens to become revived and universally accepted in some new dark age of human history. We cannot quite say that Darwinism is in the same unassailable class. Respectable opposition to it can still be mounted, and it can be argued that the current high standing of Darwinism in educated minds may not last through all future generations. . . we must acknowledge the possibility that new facts may come to light which will force our successors of the twenty-first century to abandon Darwinism or modify it beyond recognition.[351]
What Dawkins means by ‘Darwinism’ here probably co-insides with the theory of natural selection (which he brackets from ‘the fact of evolution itself’); but Dawkins affirms his faith in the survival of what he calls Core Darwinism: ‘the minimal theory that evolution is guided in adaptively non-random directions by the non-random survival of small random hereditary chances.’[352] And although Dawkins is prepared to concede that evolutionary theory might evolve in the future, he certainly isn’t prepared to admit any hint of design or purpose within biology:
The feature of living matter that most demands explanation is that it is almost unimaginably complicated in directions that convey a powerful illusion [‘appearance’ would be a less pejorative term] of deliberate design. . . Adaptations, especially complex adaptations, awake such a powerful hunger that they have traditionally provided one of the main motivations for belief in a supernatural Creator. The problem of adaptation, therefore, really was a big problem, a problem worthy of the big solution that Darwin provided. . .[353]
Note that the appearance of deliberate design is assumed to be ‘a powerful illusion’, and that this presumed ‘illusion of deliberate design’ is considered to be a ‘big problem’ precisely because it (indirectly) supports belief in ‘a supernatural Creator’! For Dawkins the atheist, the fact of evolution itself must remain staunchly naturalistic, whatever ‘new facts may come to light’![354] Dawkins’ conclusion is driven by his philosophy rather than by scientific evidence, a situation that leads him to cast aspersions on the intellectual or moral character of anyone with the timidity to call into question ‘the fact of evolution itself’ (something that can be done by doubting any of its several facets).[355] Surely we should agree with W.R. Thompson’s introduction to the centenary edition of Darwin’s Origin, which castigated ‘scientific men [who] rally to the defence of a doctrine they are unable to. . . demonstrate with scientific rigor, attempting to maintain its credit with the public by the suppression of criticism and the elimination of difficulties, [a situation that] is abnormal and undesirable in science.’[356]
The truth of the matter is that ‘more and more biologists, biochemists, and other researchers have raised serious objections to evolutionary theory in recent years.’[357]
Gordon Graham, a Professor of Philosophy at the University of Aberdeen, says he is ‘equally unsympathetic to creationism and to any rabidly anti-religious scientism.’[358] According to Graham: ‘the intellectual difficulties facing neo-Darwinism are formidable. . .’[359] He quotes David Stove, whom he calls ‘a respected philosopher writing in a professional journal’,[360] who remarks:
Most educated people nowadays. . . think of themselves as Darwinians. If they do, however, it can only be from ignorance: from not knowing enough about what Darwinism says. For Darwinism says many things, especially about our species, which are too obviously false to be believed. . . at least by any educated person who retains any capacity at all for critical thought on the subject of Darwinism.[361]
‘Suffice it to say’, concludes Graham, ‘that there are dissenting voices, and dissenting voices from within biology itself no less than from anthropology, philosophy, psychology and sociology.’[362]
According to one of the dissenting voices from within philosophy, Dr. Norman L. Geisler:
it is unreasonable to believe that intelligent life was caused by nonintelligent natural forces. . . the odds of life beginning by chance are. . . for all practical purposes, zero. . . it takes more faith to believe in evolution than it does to believe in a supernatural creator.[363]
Philosopher William Lane Craig concludes that:
in the absence of a methodological commitment to naturalism, there really does not appear to be compelling evidence for the neo-Darwinian theory. On the contrary, there seems to be pretty persuasive evidence that the neo-Darwinian account cannot be the full story.[364]
Analysing the theory of evolution without naturalistic assumptions, Alvin Plantinga, one of today’s leading philosophers, concludes: ‘that it happened is doubtful; that it is certain, however, is ridiculous.’[365]
Taken in any substantive sense, Richard Dawkins’ assertion that ‘no qualified scientist doubts that evolution is a fact’[366] is simply incorrect. For example:
the factual basis for evolution is, at best, seriously lacking. Knowledge is growing in all fields of science, but, paradoxically, there is less and less solid evidence for evolutionary mechanisms. . . The evidence for evolution being the process by which life originated and developed isn’t that convincing. The latest discoveries in biology, chemistry and other areas have raised some serious questions.[368]
Dr. Michael J. Denton’s Evolution: A Theory in Crisis was an influential critique of evolution by an agnostic scientist that contributed to the origins of Intelligent Design theory. |
In response to a recent American television series on evolution, 132 qualified scientists signed a joint statement saying: ‘We are sceptical of claims for the ability of random mutation and natural selection to account for the complexity of life.’[371]:
Signers of the statement questioning Darwinism came from throughout the US and from several other countries, representing biology, physics, chemistry, mathematics, geology, anthropology and other scientific fields. Professors and researchers at such universities as Princeton, MIT, U Penn, and Yale, as well as smaller colleges and the National Laboratories at Livermore, CA and Los Alamos, N.M., are included.[372]
As of October 2003 over 300 scientists had signed the sceptical statement.[373]
Physicist Paul Davies moved from promoting atheism in 1983 to realizing in 1984 that ‘the laws [of physics] seem themselves to be the product of exceedingly ingenious design’[374], and affirming by 1989 that this fact is ‘powerful evidence that there is something going on behind it all. The impression of design is overwhelming.’[375] In his recent book, The Origin of Life, Davies writes: ‘When I set out to write this book I was convinced that science was close to wrapping up the mysteries of life’s origin. . . Having spent a year or two researching the field I am now of the opinion that there remains a huge gulf in our understanding. . . This gulf in understanding is not merely ignorance about certain technical details, it is a major conceptual lacuna.’[376] While Davies says he is ‘not suggesting that life’s origin was a supernatural event’[377], he does think ‘that we are missing something very fundamental about the whole business’[378] and confesses: ‘My personal belief, for what it is worth, is that a fully satisfactory theory of the origin of life demands some radically new ideas.’[379], because ‘scientists are currently stumped’.[380]
‘Darwinism is too small to fit the facts it claims to explain, and ID is large enough to include a modified form of Darwinism.’ – Benjamin Wiker[381]
Philosopher of science Thomas Kuhn famously argued that major advances in science have occurred through a succession of ‘revolutions’ wherein data accumulates that does not fit with the established paradigm of ‘normal science’. At first there are, quite naturally, vigorous attempts to absorb this new information into the accepted paradigm: ‘but eventually the day comes when the paradigm can no longer stand the burden of its inner contradictions, and a new paradigm is established that makes sense of the new data in a more satisfactory way. This “revolution” in paradigm shifts then makes way for a new period of “normal science”.’[382] Design theorists believe that there is a need to subsume Darwin’s theory of evolution within the context of a scientific paradigm of intelligent design, because ‘Scientific evidence, when evaluated without an overwhelming bias toward materialism, does not support the Darwinian creation story that has effectively become a state-sponsored religion in modernist culture. On the contrary, the evidence actually supports the supposedly discredited view that an intelligent designer. . . had to be involved in biological creation.’[383]
Thomas Woodward argues that Darwinian sceptics like Michael Denton and Phillip Johnson were pre-revolutionary in that they ‘attacked Darwinism by piling up scientific anomalies and analysing the underlying philosophical assumptions’, whereas ‘Behe and Dembski have made design theory revolutionary in a Kuhnian sense by proposing a new heuristic paradigm that organizes research in a different direction.’[384] Darwin found himself trapped between seeing everything in the biological world as the result of direct and immediate intelligent design, or seeing everything as the result of an unintended evolutionary process: ‘I am conscious that I am in an utterly hopeless muddle. I cannot think that the world, as we see it, is the result of chance; and yet I cannot look at each separate thing as the result of Design.’[385] One way out of Darwin’s muddle is to hypothesise that life is the result of a combination of direct, immediate design and of an indirect, mediated process of intended evolution. This conclusion, I believe, is the best explanation of the available evidence. Darwin considered just such a hypothesis in The Origin of Species, but rejected it because, as he said, its proponents ‘do not pretend that they can define, or even conjecture, which are the [directly] created forms of life, and which are those produced by secondary laws. They admit variation as a vera causa in one case, they arbitrarily reject it in another, without assigning any distinction in the two cases.’[386] ID provides a way out of Darwin’s muddle while satisfying the implicit demand of Darwin’s objection to limiting the explanatory work done by secondary causes. Dembski’s work on CSI allows design theorists to distinguish nonarbitrarily between what secondary causes can and can’t accomplish. Behe’s concept of ‘irreducible complexity’ performs the same service, albeit in a more limited fashion. As Dembski writes:
Prior to the rise of modern science all the emphasis was on teleological guidance (typically in the form of divine design). Now the pendulum has swung to the opposite extreme, and all the emphasis is on nature’s autonomy. . . Where is the point of balance that properly respects both, and in which design becomes empirically evident? The search for that balance-point underlies all design-theoretic research. It’s not all design or all nature but a synergy of the two. Unpacking that synergy is the intelligent design research program in a nutshell.[387]
ID doesn’t hold that the neo-Darwinist theory of evolution is wholly and straightforwardly wrong; but it does suggest that it is only a partially successful theory that needs to be subsumed by a wider explanatory hypothesis of design, somewhat as Newton’s Laws were subsumed by Einstein’s: ‘In the heady early days of Newtonian mechanics,’ notes Dembski, ‘physicists thought Newton’s laws provided a total account of the constitution and dynamics of the universe. Maxwell, Einstein and Heisenberg each showed that the proper domain of Newtonian mechanics was far more constricted. So, too, the proper domain of the mutation-selection mechanism is far more constricted than most Darwinists would like to admit.’[388] As Benjamin Wiker suggests: ‘the application of materialist principles to nature has been extraordinarily fruitful, insofar as it represents a half-truth, yet it has ended ultimately in undermining its own presuppositions.’[389] Putting an interesting spin on the matter, Joshua A. Smart writes: ‘ID is in some sense an evolutionary theory. It is a theory about when evolution is inadequate.’[390]
Dembski acknowledges that ‘the Darwinian selection mechanism constitutes a fruitful idea for biology’[391] He also accepts: ‘that some speciation occurs in the manner described by Darwin. . .’[392] However: ‘Darwinism is the totalising claim that this mechanism accounts for all the diversity of life. The evidence simply does not support this claim. What evidence there is supports limited variation within fixed boundaries, or what is typically called microevolution.’[393] Moreover: ‘Macroevolution – the unlimited plasticity of organisms to diversify across all boundaries – even if true, cannot legitimately be attributed to the mutation-selection mechanism. To do so is to extrapolate the theory beyond its evidential base.’[394] Dembski affirms the existence of a ‘considerable overlap’[395] between Neo-Darwinism and Intelligent Design, and points out that: ‘intelligent design. . . does not require that every aspect of biology be designed and is fully capable of assimilating the Darwinian mechanism.’[396] As Wiker observes: ‘ID proponents. . . do not deny many of the marvellous things that Darwinism has uncovered, and so an ID account of biology would include much of what Darwinists have discovered. What they question, however, is the Darwinian assertion that such things are explicable solely as the result of. . . unguided mechanisms.’[397]
‘the ID approach is both quite natural and scientifically fruitful.’ – Benjamin Wiker[398]
Dawkins avers that: ‘Without evolution, biology is a collection of miscellaneous facts.’[399] Even if he were right about this, wouldn’t having a miscellaneous collection of facts be better than having the facts distorted by a false theoretical framework? Similarly, Theodosius Dobzhansky propounded the maxim: ‘Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution.’[400] But as Jonathan Well’s responds, ‘A true scientist would say that nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evidence.’[401]
Dawkins’ fear is doubly unfounded, because ID represents an alternative theoretical framework for biology, a fruitful new ‘paradigm’ or ‘research programme’. The ID approach is already paying dividends: ‘Design is not a science stopper. Indeed, design can foster inquiry where traditional evolutionary approaches obstruct it.’[402] For example, Wiker points out that: ‘Since the last half of the 20th century, the discovery of fine-tuning has been the impetus leading to the discovery of more fine-tuning’.[403] Wiker concludes: ‘Because the universe is irreducibly complex – not just at one level, but on successive layers of interrelated complexity – accepting the apparent complexity as real does not eliminate science but destroys materialist reductionism so that science may be released from the desire to shrink the universe and instead may inquire ever more deeply into creation. . .’[404] Scott Minnich, Associate Professor of Microbiology at the University of Idaho, is an expert on the flagellum (which he has studied for over fifteen years) who says that belief in design has given him many research insights.[405] Dembski concludes: ‘Reinstating design within science can only enrich science. . . By eschewing design, science has for too long operated with an inadequate set of conceptual categories. This has led to a constricted vision of reality, skewing how science understands not just the world but also ourselves.’[406] Woodward likewise welcomes ID as a liberating paradigm:
To be jarred awake to the powerful role that metaphysical commitments play in cosmology – especially their buttressing and protecting the Darwinian knowledge-claims – can be upsetting and unpleasant, but the cognitive health benefits are enormous. This awakening to the power of hidden metaphysical foundations is the most inevitable and immediately beneficial sort of “arousing from dogmatic slumber” that Design could achieve. Through such a rude awakening, the power of reason is newly energized. Indeed, such basic notions as rationality, intelligence, and academic freedom are given new impetus, a new breath of life. . .[407]
Darwinists once argued ‘that non-protein coding DNA are relics of once-functioning genes or useless “junk” DNA that strongly argued against design of the genome. . .’[408] However, ‘new research is beginning to overturn the view that most of the genome has no function’[409], and this is a result that verifies ID in that, unlike Darwinism, ID naturally suggests the hypothesis that so called ‘junk DNA’ will turn out to have a useful purpose:
huge stretches of genetic material dismissed in biology classrooms for generations as ‘junk DNA’ actually contain instructions essential for the growth and survival of people and other organisms. . . scientists said the new discoveries were likely to force them to abandon the term ‘junk DNA’ and send them back to the drawing board to come up with sweeping new models for how nature builds and maintains organisms.[410]
Dembski argues: ‘ID theorists should be at the forefront in unpacking the information contained within biological systems. If these systems are designed, we can expect the information to be densely packed and multi-layered (save where natural forces have attenuated the information). Dense, multi-layered embedding of information is a prediction of ID.’[411] A similar shift of opinion verifying the design hypothesis has occurred in the case of so called vestigial structures: ‘most of the structures regarded as vestigial in humans a hundred years ago are now known to have a function. . .’[412] Here again: ‘we find design encouraging scientists to look for function where evolution discourages it.’[413]
As Jonathan Wells says, ID is ‘a fledgling program, but there are some promising leads. It could have saved us 25 years if an ID approach to “junk” DNA had been pursued back when it was discovered. There are also applications now being pursued actively in embryology and the study of bacteria.’[414] Further conceptual and experimental work certainly remains to be done (after all, that’s the whole point of a scientific research programme)[415]; and only time will tell if ID can succeed in prompting a paradigm shift within the natural sciences. Whether or not it does so depends upon overcoming negative philosophical assumptions as much as upon matters of empirical evidence (indeed, it depends upon getting people to approach and evaluate the empirical evidence without a philosophical bias against design). As Dembski writes: ‘I’ll be the first to admit that intelligent design is an ambitious program and that it may not pan out. But it needs first to be fairly discussed.’[416] Paul Davies comments: ‘Dembski’s attempt to quantify design, or provide mathematical criteria for design, is extremely useful. I’m concerned that the suspicion of a hidden agenda is going to prevent that sort of work from receiving the recognition it deserves. Strictly speaking, you see, science should be judged purely on the science and not on the scientist.’[417] According to mathematician Wolfgang Smith, a Professor Emeritus at Oregon State University:
The intelligent design theory is the first rigorous refutation of Darwinism on a scientific and mathematical basis. This impresses me as a major, scientific breakthrough which, hopefully in time, will be recognized by the scientific community at large.[418]
Indeed, despite the deep-rooted naturalistic prejudices of the reigning paradigm of ‘normal science’, ID research ‘is being published and cited in the peer-reviewed scientific literature (including the biological literature)’[419], appearing in such journals as: Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, Journal of Molecular Biology, Protein Science, Journal of Theoretical Biology, Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, Proceedings of the Biological Society of Washington and Annual Review of Genetics.
While many scientists and philosophers (including Christian scientists and philosophers) continue to believe in evolution, many scientists and philosophers (including Christian scientists and philosophers) believe that the neo-Darwinian paradigm is seriously flawed. Huston Smith’s arresting verdict may prove to be prophetic: ‘Darwinism is in fact dying, and its death signals the close of our age.’[420]
Access Research Network @ www.arn.org
Axe, Douglas, ‘Extreme Functional Sensitivity to Conservative Amino Acid Changes on Enzyme Exteriors’ @ www.mrc-cpe.cam.ac.uk/publications/axe_jmb_2000.pdf
Behe, Michael J., ‘Molecular Machines: Experimental Support for the Design Inference’ @ www.arn.org/docs/behe/mb_mm92496.htm
Behe, Michael J., ‘Blind Evolution or Intelligent Design?’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&program=CSC%20-%20Scientific%20Research%20and%20Scholarship%20-%20Science&id=1205
Berlinski, David, ‘The Deniable Darwin’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=130
Craig, William Lane, ‘Review: The Design Inference – Eliminating chance through small possibilities’ @ www.leaderu.com/offices/billcraig/docs/design.html
William A. Dembski’s Design Inference Website @ www.designinference.com/
Dembski, William A., ‘Intelligent Design as a Theory of Information’ @ www.arn.org/docs/dembski/wd_idtheory.htm
Dembski, William A., ‘The Third Mode of Explanation’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=61
Dembski, William A, ‘The Logical Underpinnings of Design’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2002.10.logicalunderpinningsofID.pdf
Dembski, William A., ‘Irreducible Complexity Revisited’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2004.01.Irred_Compl_Revisited.pdf
Meyer, Stephen C., ‘DNA and Other Designs’ @ www.arn.org/docs/meyer/sm_dnaotherdesigns.htm
Meyer, Stephen C., ‘The Origin of Biological Information and the Higher Taxonomic Categories’, @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=2177&program=CSC%20-%20Scientific%20Research%20and%20Scholarship%20-%20Science
Meyer, Stephen C., et al, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’ @ www.discovery.org/articleFiles/PDFs/Cambrian.pdf
Minnich, Scott A. & Stephen C. Meyer, ‘Genetic Analysis of Coordinate Flagellar and Type II Regulatory Circuits in Pathogenic Bacteria ’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=148
Moreland, J. P., ‘Is Science a Threat or a Help to Faith? A Look at the Concept of Theistic Science’ @ www.afterall.net/index.php/papers/18
Moreland, J. P., ‘Complimentarity, Agency Theory, and the God-of-the-Gaps’ @ www.afterall.net/index.php/papers/490579
Moreland J. P., ‘Scientific Creationism, Science, and Conceptual Problems’ @ www.afterall.net/index.php/papers/490578
Newman, Robert C. et al, ‘The Status of Evolution as a Scientific Theory’ @ www.arn.org/docs/newman/rn_statusofevolution.htm
Plantinga, Alvin, ‘Methodological Naturalism?’ @ http://id-www.ucsb.edu/fscf/library/plantinga/mn/home.html
Plantinga, Alvin, ‘When Faith and Reason Clash: Evolution and the Bible’ @ www.asa3.org/ASA/dialogues/Faith-reason/CRS9-91Plantinga1.html
Plantinga, Alvin, ‘Evolution, Neutrality, and Anticedent Probability: a Reply to Van Till and McMullen’ @ www.asa3.org/ASA/dialogues/Faith-reason/CRS9-91Plantinga2.html
Plantinga, Alvin, ‘On Rejecting the Theory of Common Ancestry: A Reply to Hasker’ @ www.asa3.org/ASA/dialogues/Faith-reason/PSCF12-92Plantinga.html
Wells, Jonathan, ‘Survival of the Fakest’ @ www.discovery.org/articleFiles/PDFs/survivalOfTheFakest.pdf
Williams, Peter S., ‘A Rough Guide to Creation and Evolution’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_roughguidetocreationandevolution.htm
Williams, Peter S., ‘Darwins’ Rottweiler & the Public Understanding of Scientism’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_dawkinsfallacies.htm
Williams, Peter S., ‘Reviewing the Reviewers: Pigliucci et al on “Darwin’s Rottweiler & the public understanding of science”’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_pigliucci_reviewingreviewers.htm
Williams, Peter S., ‘Design Arguments: Amazon Listmania List’ @ www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/tg/listmania/list-browse/-/3CKOYI2H94VQU/ref=cm_aya_av.lm_more/002-9805224-1419262
Beckwith, Francis J., Law, Darwinism, and Public Education: The Establishment Clause and the Challenge of Intelligent Design, (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2003)
Behe, Michael J., Darwin’s Black Box, (Free Press, 1998)
Behe, Michael J., et al, Science and Evidence for Design in the Universe, (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2000)
Campbell, John Angus & Stephen C. Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 2003)
Dembski, William A., The Design Revolution: Answering the Toughest Questions about Intelligent Design, (IVP, 2004)
Dembski, William A., No Free Lunch: Why Specified Complexity Cannot be Purchased without Intelligence, (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001)
Dembski, William A. (ed.), Uncommon Dissent: Intellectuals Who Find Darwinism Unconvincing, (Wilmington, Del: ISI Books, 2004)
Dembski, William A. and James M. Kushner (ed.’s), Signs of Intelligence, (Grand Rapids , Michigan: Brazos Press, 2001)
Johnson, Philip E., Darwin on Trial, (Downers Grove: IVP)
Moreland, J.P (ed.), The Creation Hypothesis, (Downers Grove, Illinois: IVP, 1994)
Overman, Dean L., A Case Against Accident and Self-Organization, (Rowman & Littlefield, 1997)
Ratzsch, Del, Science & Its Limits: The Natural Sciences in Christian Perspective (Leicester: Apollos, 2000)
Strobel, Lee, The Case for a Creator, (Zondervan, 2004)
Thaxton, Charles B. et al, Mystery of Life’s Origins: Reassessing Current Theories, (Ashgate, 1987)
Wells, Jonathan, Icons of Evolution, (Washington: Regnery Publishing, 2000)
Williams, Peter S., I Wish I Could Believe in Meaning: A Response to Nihilism, (Damaris, 2004)
Woodward, Thomas, Doubts About Darwin: A History of Intelligent Design, (Grand Rapids: Baker, 2003)
On Video or DVD: Unlocking the Mysteries of Life (Illustrated Media)
[1] Beckwith, Francis J, Law, Darwinism, and Public Education: The Establishment Clause and the Challenge of Intelligent Design, (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2003), p. xiii.
[2] cf. Craig, William Lane, ‘Review: The Design Inference – Eliminating chance through small possibilities’ @ www.leaderu.com/offices/billcraig/docs/design.html; Dembski, William A., ‘The Third Mode of Explanation’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=61; Dembski, William A., ‘Intelligent Design as a Theory of Information’ @ www.arn.org/docs/dembski/wd_idtheory.htm; Dembski, William A, ‘The Logical Underpinnings of Design’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2002.10.logicalunderpinningsofID.pdf; Dembski, William A., No Free Lunch: Why Specified Complexity Cannot be Purchased without Intelligence, (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001)
[3] Behe, Michael J., ‘Blind Evolution or Intelligent Design?’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=1205
[4] Craig, ‘Review: The Design Inference – Eliminating chance through small possibilities’ @ www.leaderu.com/offices/billcraig/docs/design.html
[5] cf. Ross, Hugh, ‘Probability for a Life Support Body’ @ www.reasons.org/resources/apologetics/design_evidences/20020502_life_support_body_prob.shtml?main; Guillermo Gonzalez and Jay Richards, The Privileged Planet: How Our Place in the Cosmos Is Designed for Discovery, (Regnery, Jan. 2004); Jimmy H. Davies & Harry L. Poe, Designer Universe: Intelligent Design and the Existence of God, (Broadman & Holman, 2002)
[6] cf. Stephen C. Meyer, ‘DNA and Other Designs’ @ www.arn.org/docs/meyer/sm_dnaotherdesigns.htm; Dean L. Overman, A Case Against Accident and Self-Organization, (Rowman & Littlefield, 1997)
[7] cf. Michael J. Behe, ‘Molecular Machines: Experimental Support for the Design Inference’ @ www.arn.org/docs/behe/mb_mm92496.htm; ‘Darwin Under the Microscope’ @ http://catholiceducation.org/articles/science/sc0017.html; Darwin’s Black Box (Free Press, 1998); William A. Dembski, No Free Lunch: Why Specified Complexity Cannot be Purchased without Intelligence (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001); ‘Irreducible Complexity Revisited’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2004.01.Irred_Compl_Revisited.pdf; ‘Still Spinning Just Fine: A Response to Ken Miller’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2003.02.Miller_Response.htm; See E. Coli swimming using flagella @ www.mtmi.vu.lt/pfk/funkc_dariniai/nanostructures/bacteria.htm
[8] cf. Stephen C. Meyer, ‘The Origin of Biological Information and the Higher Taxonomic Categories’, @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=2177&program=CSC%20-%20Scientific%20Research%20and%20Scholarship%20-%20Science; Kurt P. Wise, ‘The Origin of Life’s Major Groups’, in J.P. Moreland (ed.), The Creation Hypothesis, (IVP, 1994); Robert F. Dehaan and John L. Wiester, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: The Fossil Record and Intelligent Design’, in William A. Dembski & James M. Kushiner (ed.’s), Signs of Intelligence, (Brazos Press, 2001); & Stephen C. Meyer, Marcus Ross, Paul Nelson and Paul Chien, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’, in John Angus Campbell & Stephen C. Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan State University Press, 2003) @ www.discovery.org/articleFiles/PDFs/Cambrian.pdf
[9] Beckwith, op cit, p. xvi-xvii.
[11] ARN guide to Evolution @ www.arn.org/docs/pbsevolution/vguide.pdf
[12] Dawkins, A Devil’s Chaplain, p. 219.
[13] Krishtalka, Leonard, quoted by Glenn Branch in ‘Human Nature After Darwin by Janet Radcliffe Richards’, Philosophy Now, 40, March/April 2003, p. 44.
[14] ibid, p. 33.
[15] Gould, Stephen Jay, Natural History, March 1997, quoted Woodward, op cit, p. 210.
[16] ARN guide to Evolution, op cit.
[17] John Angus Campbell, ‘Why Are We Still Debating Darwinism?, Campbell & Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan University Press, 2003), p. xxvi.
[18] ‘Intelligent design: The New “Big Tent” for Evolution’s critics’, University of Wisconsin – Madison News, February 19, 2004.
[19] Wiker, Moral Darwinism, p. 77.
[20] Woodward, op cit, p. 196, my italics.
[21] Dembski, ‘What Every Theologian Should Know about Creation, Evolution, and Design’, op cit.
[22] Johnson, Phillip E., Darwin on Trail, (Downers Grove, IVP, 19932), p. 14 & 115.
[23] Woodward, Appendix 2, op cit, p. 223.
[24] Johnson, Reason in the Balance, (Downers Grove: IVP, 1995), p. 74.
[25] cf. Williams, Peter S., ‘A Rough Guide to Creation and Evolution’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_roughguidetocreationandevolution.htm; John J. Davis, (ed.), Three Views on Creation and Evolution, (Zondervan, 1999).
[26] Beckwith, op cit, p. 153.
[27] Woodward, Thomas, Doubts about Darwin: A History of Intelligent Design, (Grand Rapids: Baker, 2003), p. 10 & 20.
[28] cf. Dembski, ‘Is Intelligent Design a Form of Natural Theology?’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2001.03.ID_as_nat_theol.htm
[29] Beckwith, op cit, p. 164.
[30] Dembski, ‘Does the Design Argument show there is a God?’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2003.08.Apol_Stdy_Bib_Entry.htm
[31] Behe, Michael J., ‘The Modern Intelligent Design Hypothesis’, Philosophia Christi, Series 2, Volume 3, Number 1, 2001, p. 165.
[32] Dembski, ‘Skepticism's Prospects for Unseating Intelligent Design’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2002.06.Skepticism_CSICOP.htm
[33] Scientists who accept Fred Hoyle’s theory of ‘directed-panspermia’ (illustrated in the film Mission to Mars), the idea that life was engineered and/or brought to earth by extra-terrestrials, might subscribe to ID. Of course, this interpretation of intelligent design theory faces an awkward explanatory regress in explaining the origin of the aliens. cf. Lee Elliot Major, ‘Big Enough to Bury Darwin’ @ http://education.guardian.co.uk/higher/physicalscience/story/0,9836,541468,00.html; Michael J. Behe, ‘The God of Science’ @ www.arn.org/docs/behe/mb_godofscience.htm
[34] Dembski, ‘Is Intelligent Design a Form of Natural Theology?’, op cit.
[35] ARN guide to Evolution.
[36] Wiker, op cit, p. 77.
[37] Nichols, Terence, The Sacred Cosmos, (Grand Rapids: Brazos Press, 2003), p. 61.
[38] Plato, The Laws, book X.
[40] cf. Plantinga, Alvin, ‘Methodological Naturalism?’ @ http://id-www.ucsb.edu/fscf/library/plantinga/mn/home.html; Craig, William Lane and Moreland, J. P., Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview (Downers Grove: IVP, 2003); Moreland, J.P (ed.), The Creation Hypothesis, (Downers Grove, Illinois: IVP, 1994)
[41] Dawkins, Richard, The Blind Watchmaker, p. 151, my emphasis.
[42] Lewontin, Richard, ‘Billions and Billions of Demons’, New York Review of Books, January 9, 1997.
[43] Dembski, William A., ‘What Every Theologian Should Know about Creation, Evolution and Design’, p. 6, my italics.
[44] Ratzsch, Del, Science & Its Limits, (Leicester: Apollos, 2000), p. 123-124.
[45] Witham, Larry, By Design, (San Francisco: Encounter Books, 2003), p. 143.
[46] Williams, Peter S., ‘Reviewing the Reviewers: Pigliucci et al on “Darwin’s Rottweiler & the public understanding of science”’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_pigliucci_reviewingreviewers.htm; Moreland, J. P., ‘Complimentarity, Agency Theory, and the God-of-the-Gaps’ @ www.afterall.net/index.php/papers/490579
[47] DeWolf et al, ‘Teaching the Controversy: Is it Science, Religion, or Speech?’, John Angus Campbell & Stephen C. Meyer’s (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan State University Press, 2003), p. 79.
[48] Moreland, J.P., ‘Theistic Science & Methodological Naturalism’, Moreland (ed.), The Creation Hypothesis, p. 55.
[49] Dembski, Mere Creation, op cit, p. 17. cf. Peter S. Williams, ‘Christianity, Space & Aliens’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_christianityspaceandaliens.htm
[50] Beckwith, op cit, p. 107.
[51] Michael Ruse, Can a Darwinian be a Christian?, p. 101.
[52] Michael Ruse, quoted by John Angus Campbell, ‘Intelligent Design, Darwinism, and Public Education Philosophy’, in Campbell & Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan State University Press, 2003), p. 30.
[53] John Angus Campbell, op cit, p. xii.
[54] Dembski, Mere Creation, (Downers Grove: IVP, 1996), p. 17.
[55] Dembski, ‘Three Frequently Asked Questions About Intelligent Design’, op cit.
[56] Dembski, op cit, p. 17.
[57] Marcus R. Ross, Intelligent Design and Young Earth Creationism – investigating nested hierarchies of philosophy and belief’ @ http://gsa.confex.com/gsa/2003AM/finalprogram/abstract_58668.htm
[58] Kaita, Robert, ‘Cosmological Principle & Cosmic Imperative?’, in William A. Dembski (ed.), Mere Creation, op. cit., p. 400. cf. Crop Circle News @ www.cropcirclenews.com/ & Peter Sorensen Homepage @ http://cropcircleconnector.com/Sorensen/PeterSorensen99.html
[59] Picture from BBC NEWS @ http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/england/wiltshire/3552168.stm, cf. Peter Sorensen Homepage, 2004 images @ http://cropcircleconnector.com/Sorensen/2004/2004AD.html!
[60] Kaita, op cit.
[61] Bocarsly, Andrew and Kaita, Robert, in Woodward, op. cit., p.212.
[62] Meyer, Steven C., ‘The Explanatory Power of Design’ in William A. Dembski (ed.), Mere Creation (Downers Grove: IVP, 1998).
[63] Dawkins, Richard, Climbing Mount Improbable (Viking, 1996), p.259.
[64] Dawkins, Richard, ‘Darwin’s Dangerous Disciple’ at www.skeptic.com/03.4.miele-dawkins-iv.html
[65] Dawkins, Richard, A Devil’s Chaplain (London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson, 2003), p.248.
[66] Dawkins, ‘Darwin’s Dangerous Disciple’ at www.skeptic.com/03.4.miele-dawkins-iv.html
[67] Wiker, Benjamin, op. cit.
[68] Wald, George,‘Innovation and Biology’, Scientific American, 199 (Sept. 1958): 100.
[69] Johnson, Phillip E., ‘Positional Paper on Darwinism’, in Woodward, Appendix 2, op. cit., p.219.
[70] Kerkut, G. A., Implications of Evolution (Pergamon Press), p.150, quoted by John Blanchard, in Does God Believe in Atheists? (Darlington: Evangelical Press, 2000), p. 297.
[71] cf. Meyer, Stephen C., ‘DNA and Other Designs’ @ www.arn.org/docs/meyer/sm_dnaotherdesigns.htm; Overman, Dean L., A Case Against Accident and Self-Organization, (Rowman & Littlefield, 1997)
[72] Johnson, Phillip E., ‘What is Darwinism’, Objection Sustained, (Downers Grove: IVP, 1998), p. 33.
[73] Craig, William Lane, Philosophy of Religion: A Reader and Guide (Edinburgh University Press, 2002), p.72.
[74] Dembski, ‘Another Way to Detect Design?’ @ www.arn.org/docs/dembski/wd_responsetowiscu.htm
[75] The Monkey Shakespeare Simulator @ http://user.tninet.se/~ecf599g/aardasnails/java/Monkey/webpages/
[76] The Monkey Shakespeare Simulator @ http://user.tninet.se/~ecf599g/aardasnails/java/Monkey/webpages/
[77] The simulated monkeys typed: ‘1. Citizen. Before wZgJ 8GPxwFnwvG&iX4tKfo("2ny!3Pp. . .’ which matched: ‘1. Citizen. Before we proceed any further, heare me speake. . .’ Interestingly, it took 2,182,280,000 billion billion monkey-years to produce 18 letters from ‘Timon of Athens’ (‘Poet. Good day SirBf4I.” “M 'O.)jdtQ4Q].IPRe&BSJF. . .’ matched ‘Poet. Good day Sir Pain. I am glad y'are well . .) & 42,162,500,000 billion billion monkey-years to produce 19 letters from ‘Two Gentlemen of Verona’ (‘VALENTINE. Cease to1d0r:eFLP0FRjWK78aXzVOwm)-';8.t. . .’ matched: ‘VALENTINE. Cease to persuade, my loving Proteus. . .’)
[78] Dembski, Intelligent Design, (Downers Grove: IVP, 1999), p. 166.
[79] Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker, (London: Penguin, 1988), p. 139.
[80] Dembski, No Free Lunch, (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2002), p. 157.
[81] ibid, p. 86.
[82] ibid, p. 93.
[83] Dawkins, Climbing Mount Improbable, (TSP: Viking, 1996), p. 4
[84] ibid, p. 3.
[85] ibid.
[86] Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker, op cit, Preface, p. x.
[87] ibid, p. 4-5. This statement embodies the false dilemma that either design or evolution is true, when these options are in fact logically compatible. cf. Stephen’s Guide to the Logical Fallacies, ‘False Dilemma’ @ www.intrepidsoftware.com/fallacy/fd.php (05/04/2004)
[88] ibid, p. 3.
[89] ibid.
[90] ibid, p. 4.
[91] cf. Stephen’s Guide to the Logical Fallacies, ‘Equivocation’ @ www.intrepidsoftware.com/fallacy/equiv.php
[92] Keith, Alan, Philosophy Now, Issue 45, March/April 2004, Letters, p. 42.
[93] cf. Williams, Peter S., ‘Darwin’s Rottweiler & the public understanding of science’, Philosophy Now Issue 44 (Jan/Feb 2004)
[94] Massimo Pigliucci is associate Professor at the University of Tennessee in Knoxville, where he teaches ecology and evolutionary biology. Professor Pigliucci has a PhD in botany from the University of Connecticut and a PhD in philosophy from the University of Tennessee. Pigliucci has published many technical papers and two books on evolutionary biology (Phenotypic Evolution, with Carl Schlichting, and Phenotypic Plasticity: Beyond Nature vs. Nurture.) He has been awarded the Oak Ridge National Labs award for excellence in research (several times), and has won the prestigious Dobzhensky prize from the Society for the Study of Evolution (of which he is now vice president). A self-styled ‘skeptic’, Pigliucci’s articles have appeared in: The Skeptic, Free Inquiry, Philosophy Now and The Philosophers Magazine. cf. www.infidels.org/library/modern/massimo_pigliucci/index.shtml
[95] Pigliucci, Massimo, et al, ‘The Alleged Fallacies of Evolutionary Theory’, published in Philosophy Now Issue 46 (May/June 2004).
[96] ibid
[97] ibid
[98] ibid
[99] For a detailed response to Pigliucci et al, cf. Williams, Peter S., ‘Reviewing the Reviewers: Pigliucci et al on “Darwin’s Rotweiller and the Public Understanding of Science”’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_pigliucci_reviewingreviewers.htm
[100] Koons, Robert C., ‘The Check Is In The Mail: Why Darwinism Fails to Inspire Confidence’, in Dembski, William A., (ed.), Uncommon Dissent, (2004), p. 7.
[101] ibid.
[102] ibid.
[103] ibid.
[104] ibid.
[105] ibid.
[106] Dawkins, op cit, p. 3.
[107] ibid, p. 3.
[108] ibid.
[109] ibid.
[110] ibid, my italics.
[111] ibid.
[112] Pictures from Bradley, Walter L., ‘Is There Scientific Evidence for God’ @ www.leaderu.com/real/ri9403/evidence.html
[113] Dawkins, op cit, p. 3.
[114] Richard Dawkins, in interview with Keith Ward, The Turn of The Tide, (BBC, 1986), p. 28, my italics.
[115] Behe, ‘Blind Evolution or Intelligent Design?’
[116] Stephen Hawking, quoted by John Boslough, Masters of Time – Cosmology at the End of Innocence, (New York: Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, 1992), p. 55.
[117] cf. Williams, ‘Reviewing the Reviewers: Pigliucci et al on “Darwin’s Rotweiller and the Public Understanding of Science”’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_pigliucci_reviewingreviewers.htm
[118] Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker, op cit.
[119] Adams, Douglas, The Salmon of Doubt (Pan Books, 2003), p.131.
[120] Overman, A Case Against Accident and Self-Organization (Rowman & Littlefield, 1997), p. 128.
[121] Moreland, J. P. and Craig, William Lane, Philosophical Foundations For A Christian Worldview, p.487.
[122] ibid, p. 486.
[123] ibid.
[124] J.P. Moreland, Scaling the Secular City, (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1987).
[125] cf. Stephen C. Meyer, ‘Evidence for Design in Physics and Biology’ in Michael Behe, William A. Dembski & Stephen C. Meyer, Science and Evidence for Design in the Universe, (San Francisco, Ignatius, 2000), p. 60.
[126] cf. Jimmy H. Davies and Harry L. Poe, Designer Universe, (Nashville: Broadman & Holman, 2002), p. 85.
[127] Penrose, Roger, The Emperor’s New Mind, (New York, Oxford, 1989), p. 344.
[128] Page’s calculation is quoted by L. Stafford Betty and Bruce Cordell, ‘The Anthropic Teleological Argument’, International Philosophical Quarterly 27, no. 4., (December 1987).
[129] Fred Hoyle, as quoted in Fred Hereen, Show Me God, (Search Light Publishing, 1995), p. 179.
[130] Clark, Stephen R. L., God, Religion and Reality (London: SPCK, 1998), p.106.
[131] Dembski, op cit, p. 16-17.
[132] Moreland, J.P. & William Lane Craig, Philosophical Foundations For A Christian Worldview, (Downer’s Grove: IVP, 2003), p. 62.
[133] Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker, op cit, p. 9.
[134] Dawkins, ‘Darwin’s Dangerous Disciple’ at www.skeptic.com/03.4.miele-dawkins-iv.html
[135] cf. Williams, ‘Reviewing the Reviewers: Pigliucci et al on “Darwin’s Rotweiller and the Public Understanding of Science”’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_pigliucci_reviewingreviewers.htm
[136] Philosophy Now, Issue 47, August/September 2004, p. 22
[137] ibid.
[138] Asimov, Isaac, Please Explain, quoted by Alan Hayward, in Does God Exist? Science says ‘Yes’ (Basingstoke: Lakeland, 1979), p.76.
[139] Hayward, op cit., p.76.
[140] Wiker, Benjamin, ‘Does Science Point to God?’ at www.arn.org/docs2/news/doessciencepointtogod040903.htm
[141] Woodward, Thomas, Doubts About Darwin (Grand Rapids: Baker, 2003), p.44.
[142] Overman, Dean L., A Case Against Accident and Self-Organization (Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), p.41.
[143] Overman, op. cit., p. 41.
[144] Denton, Michael, Evolution: A Theory in Crisis (Woodbine House, 1996), p.262.
[145] Varghese, The Wonder of the World, op cit, p. 276.
[146] Yockey, Hurbert P., ‘A calculation of the Probability of Spontaneous Biogenesis by Information Theory,’ Journal of Theoretical Biology, 67, (1977), p. 377.
[147] Overman, op. cit., p. 40.
[148] Denyse O’Leary, By Design or by Chance? The Growing Controversy on the Origins of Life in the Universe, (Minneapolis: Ausberg Books, 2004), p. 8.
[149] Beadle, George, ‘The Language of the Gene’ in The Language of Science (New York: Basic Books, 1963), p.62.
[150] Delbruck, Max, interview in Horace Freeland Judson, The Eighth Day of Creation (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1979), p.213.
[151] Blanchard, John, Does God Believe in Atheists? (Darlington: Evangelical Press, 2000), p. 292.
[152] Varghese, op cit, p. 276.
[153] Quoted by Varghese, The Wonder of the World, p. 278.
[154] Sarfati, Jonathan, Refuting Evolution 2 (Master Books, 2003), p.58.
[155] Bradley, Walter L., in Strobel, The Case for Faith, op. cit., p.111. Bradley is using ‘faith’ in the same sense that Dawkins uses the term to mean belief without or against evidence.
[156] Dawkins, Richard, Climbing Mount Improbable (Viking, 1996), p.259.
[157] Dawkins, Richard, ‘Darwin’s Dangerous Disciple’ at www.skeptic.com/03.4.miele-dawkins-iv.html
[158] Dawkins, Richard, A Devil’s Chaplain (London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson, 2003), p.248.
[159] Dawkins is not alone in his leap of faith. For example, Harvard biologist George Wald dismissed the design explanation for life but candidly admitted: ‘I will not believe that philosophically because I do not want to believe in God. Therefore, I choose to believe in that which I know is scientifically impossible: spontaneous generation [that life arose from non-living matter] arising to evolution.’ – ‘Innovation and Biology’, Scientific American, 199 (Sept. 1958): 100.
[160] Johnson, Phillip E., ‘Positional Paper on Darwinism’, in Woodward, Appendix 2, op. cit., p.219.
[161] Wiker, op. cit.
[162] Bradley, Walter L., in Strobel, The Case for Faith (Zondervan, 2000), p.100.
[163] Kerkut, G. A., Implications of Evolution (Pergamon Press), p.150, quoted by John Blanchard, in Does God Believe in Atheists? (Darlington: Evangelical Press, 2000), p.297.
[164] Shapiro, Robert, Origins: A Skeptic’s Guide to the Creation of Life on Earth (New York: Summit Books, 1986), p.112.
[165] Schidlowsky, Manfred, quoted by Overman, op. cit., p.43.
[166] Overman, ibid.
[167] Meyer, Steven C., ‘The Explanatory Power of Design’ in William A. Dembski (ed.), Mere Creation (Downers Grove: IVP, 1998).
[168] Thaxton, Charles, Bradley, Walter and Olsen, Roger, The Mystery of Life’s Origin (Ashgate, 1987), p.185.
[169] Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker, (London: Penguin, 1988), p. 139.
[170] Dawkins, op cit, p. 260.
[171] ibid.
[172] Ross, Hugh, ‘Astronomical Evidences for a Personal, Transcendent God’, in J. P. Moreland (ed.), The Creation Hypothesis (Downers Grove: IVP, 1994), p.170.
[173] Faulkner, Danny R., in John F. Ashton (ed.), On the Seventh Day (Green Forrest: Master Books, 2002), p.107.
[174] Wiker, op cit.
[175] cf. Ross, Hugh, ‘Fine Tuning of Physical Life Support Body’ @ www.reasons.org/resources/apologetics/design_evidences/20020502_solar_system_design.shtml?main & ‘Probability for a Life Support Body’ @ www.reasons.org/resources/apologetics/design_evidences/20020502_life_support_body_prob.shtml?main
[176] Ross, Hugh, ‘Astronomical Evidences for a Personal, Transcendent God’, op. cit., p.169-170.
[177] Ward, Peter and Brownlee, Don, Rare Earth (New York: Springer-Verlag, 2000), p.35, 37.
[178] Meyer, Stephen C., ‘Evidence for design in Physics and Biology’, in Science and Evidence for Design in the Universe (San Francisco: Ignatius, 2000), p.75.
[179] Dawkins, Richard, The Blind Watchmaker (London: Penguin, 1990), p.139.
[180] Wickramasinghe, Chandra, cited in Roy Abraham Varghese (ed.), The Intellectuals Speak about God (Regnery Gateway), p.33, quoted by John Blanchard, op. cit., p.298.
[181] Behe, Michael J., ‘The Modern Intelligent Design Hypothesis’, Philosophia Christi, Series 2, Volume 3, Number 1, 2001, p.177.
[182] ibid.
[183] Ward, Keith, God, Faith & The New Millennium (Oxford: OneWorld, 1999), p.110.
[184] Hoyle, Fred and Wickramasinghe, Chandra, Evolution from Space (Dent, 1981), p.24-148.
[185] ibid, p.130.
[186] Geisler, Norman L. and J. Kerby Anderson, Origin Science, (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1987), p. 159 -164.
[187] ibid, p. 159 -164.
[188] Meyer, Stephen C., ‘The Origin of Biological Information and the Higher Taxonomic Categories’, Proceedings of the Biological Society of Washington (volume 117, no. 2, 2004, pp. 213-239).
[189] cf. Williams, Peter S., ‘Undermining Richard Norman on “Why Science Undermines Religion”’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_underminingrichardnorman.htm
[190] ibid
[191] ibid
[192] Zimmer, Carl, Evolution, (New York: Harper Collins, 2001), p. 325.
[193] cf. Williams, Peter S., ‘Undermining Richard Norman on “Why Science Undermines Religion”’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_underminingrichardnorman.htm
[194] David Berlinksi, ‘Berlinksi replies to H. Allen Orr’, in Uncommon Dissent, op cit, p. 286.
[195] Robert C. Newman et al, What’s Darwin Got to Do With It?, (IVP), p. 39.
[196] ibid, p. 23.
[197] cf. Ahuja, Anjana, ‘A Species is Born: Scientists believe that they may be witnessing evolution in action on our northern coastline’, The Times, T2, 22 July 2004, p. 14. This report concerns two varieties or morphs of Yorkshire periwinkles (mid-shore and high-shore) that may be in the process of becoming separate species, in that they are currently not keen on breeding with each other: ‘The problem with watching just one freeze-frame [of a presumed evolutionary history]. . . is not knowing what came before or what will happen in the future. For example, it is possible, though unlikely, that the reverse is happening, and that two species are merging into one.’
[198] David DeWolf, Stephen C. Meyer and Mark E. DeForrest, ‘Teaching the Controversy: Is it Science, Religion, or Speech?’, in John Angus Campbell & Stephen C. Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan State University Press, 2003), p. 66.
[199] Jonathan Wells, in Lee Strobel, The Case for a Creator, (Zondervan, 2004), p. 43.
[200] Koons, op cit, p. 4.
[201] Dehaan, Robert F. and John L. Wiester, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: The Fossil Record and Intelligent Design’, in William A. Dembski & James M. Kushiner (ed.s’), Signs of Intelligence, (Brazos Press, 2001), p. 150.
[202] Kitts, David B., ‘Paleontology and Evolutionary Theory’, Evolution, vol. 28, 1974, p. 467.
[203] Kitts, ibid.
[204] Sunderland, Luther, Darwin’s Enigma, (Master Books, 1998), p. 11.
[205] Ankerberg, John & John Weldon, ‘Rational Inquiry & the Force of Scientific Data: Are New Horizons Emerging?, in J.P. Moreland (ed), The Creation Hypothesis, (IVP, 1994), p. 278.
[206] Niles Eldridge, The Myths of Human Evolution, (Columbia University Press, 1982), p. 59. The theory of ‘punctuated equilibrium’, with which Eldridge is associated, ‘is really more of an observation – based on the fossil record, which shows appearance of new species (for example, in the Cambrian explosion) than it is a theory in the usual sense’, and while ‘there has been a major ongoing debate among evolutionists themselves on the likelihood of the punctuated equilibrium model verses the traditional gradualistic one’ it seems that ‘the traditional gradualism model still has strong support’; and in any case ‘Whichever model evolutionists choose to suggest. . . the lack of a single example of a real transition is evidence enough that the fossil record does not support evolution.’ (Ralph O. Muncaster, Dismantling Evolution, p. 86-87.) Phillip E. Johnson writes: ‘Most evolutionary biologists do not accept Eldridge and Gould’s hypothesis that evolutionary change is closely associated with speciation. . . Speciation and change in form. . . seem to be different phenomena. . . For these and other reasons, orthodox neo-Darwinists prefer to explain sudden appearance on the traditional basis of gaps in the fossil record. . .’ (Darwin on Trial, p. 52-53.) For a critique of both Darwinian gradualism and punctuated equilibrium in relation to the fossil record cf. Stephen C. Meyer, Marcus Ross, Paul Nelson and Paul Chien, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’, @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=29 and in John Angus Campbell & Stephen C. Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan State University Press, 2003), p. 338.
[207] David Raup, ‘Conflicts between Darwin and Paleontology’, Field Museum of Natural History Bulletin, January, 1979.
[208] Muncaster, op cit, p. 81.
[209] The Brown University News Bureau, February 25, 1999; http://brown.edu/Administration/News Bureau/1998-99/98-077.html
[210] Johnson, Phillip E., ‘Evolution as Dogma’, in Uncommon Dissent, op cit, p. 26.
[211] Hunter, Cornelius G., ‘Why Evolution Fails the Test of Science’, in Uncommon Dissent, op cit, p. 206.
[212] Eldridge, Niles, Harper’s Magazine (February, 1985), p. 60.
[213] Stanley, Steve M., Macroevolution, p. 59, quoted by Ankerberg & Weldon, op cit.
[214] Nelson, Gareth, quoted by Johnson, ‘Evolution as Dogma’, op cit.
[215] Carroll, Robert, Patterns and Processes of Vertebrate Evolution, (Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 8.
[216] Hartwig, Mark, ‘Challenging Darwin’s Myths’, in James P. Gills & Tom Woodward (ed.’s), Darwinism under the Microscope , p. 26.
[217] Quoted by Woodward, Tom, ‘Of Canadian Oddballs and Chinese Monsters’, in James P. Gills & Tom Woodward (ed.’s), Darwinism under the Microscope, (Charisma House, 2002), p. 105.
[218] Stephen C. Meyer, Marcus Ross, Paul Nelson and Paul Chien, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’, @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=29 and in John Angus Campbell & Stephen C. Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan State University Press, 2003), p. 338.
[219] Beckwith, Francis J., Law, Darwinism, And Public Education, (Rowman & Littlefield, 2003), p. 118. cf. Kurt P. Wise, ‘The Origin of Life’s Major Groups’, in J.P. Moreland (ed.), The Creation Hypothesis, (IVP, 1994); Robert F. Dehaan & John L. Wiester, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: The Fossil Record and Intelligent Design’, in William A. Dembski & James M. Kushiner (ed.s’), Signs of Intelligence, (Brazos Press, 2001); & Stephen C. Meyer, Marcus Ross, Paul Nelson & Paul Chien, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’, in John Angus Campbell & Stephen C. Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan State University Press, 2003) & @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=29
[220] cf. ‘Intelligent Design Article Sparks Controversy’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=2190&program=CSC%20-%20Science%20and%20Education%20Policy%20-%20News%20and%20Articles; Mark Hartwig, ‘Bitten’ @ www.arn.org/docs/wedge/mh_wedge_040923.htm; ‘Darwinists Trying to Squelch Intelligent Design Debate’ @ http://headlines.agapepress.org/archive/9/142004a.asp; ‘One Long Bluff’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=2223&program=CSC%20-%20Scientific%20Research%20and%20Scholarship%20-%20Science%20-%20MainPage & ‘The Meyer’s Paper Controversy’ @ www.arn.org/docs2/news/Magnuson091604.htm
[221] McDonald, J.F., ‘The molecular basis of adaptation: a critical review of relevant ideas and observations’, Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 14:77-102, 1983, p. 93.
[222] Meyer et al, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’, @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=29 and in John Angus Campbell & Stephen C. Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, (Michigan State University Press, 2003), p. 323–402.
[223] ibid.
[224] ibid.
[225] ibid.
[226] Varghese, op cit, p. 289.
[227] Johnson, Darwin on Trial, op cit, p. 27.
[228] cf. Williams, ‘Undermining Richard Norman on “Why Science Undermines Religion”’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_underminingrichardnorman.htm
[229] Thompson, Keith Stewart, ‘Macroevolution: The Morphological Problem’, American Zoologist 32 (1992): 106-112.
[230] Hull, David L., Darwin and his Critics, p. 7, quoted by Ankerberg & Weldon, op cit.
[231] Colson, Charles and Nancy Pearcey, Developing a Christian Worldview of Science And Evolution, (Tyndale House, 2001), p. 73.
[232] Hunter, Cornelius G., Darwin’s Proof, (Brazos Press, 2003), p. 60.
[233] Dehaan and Wiester, op cit, p. 150.
[234] Meyer et al, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’, @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=29 and in John Angus Campbell & Stephen C. Meyer (ed.’s), Darwinism, Design, And Public Education, op cit, p. 354.
[235] Hunter, ‘Why Evolution Fails the Test of Science’, in Uncommon Dissent, op cit, p. 203.
[236] Wells, in Strobel, op cit, p. 46.
[237] Johnson, Phillip, in Woodward, Appendix 2, op. cit., p.219-220.
[238] Ralph O. Muncaster, Dismantling Evolution, (harvest House, 2003), p. 113.
[239] Darwin, op cit, p. 184.
[240] Dawkins, Richard, ‘Darwin Triumphant’, A Devil’s Chaplain, op. cit., p.86.
[241] Dawkins, Climbing Mount Improbable, op. cit.
[242] Vogel, Steven, Cat’s Paws and Catapults (Penguin, 1998), p.23.
[243] Gould, Stephen Jay, ‘Is a new and general theory of evolution emerging?’, Paleobiology, Vol. 6 (1), January 1980, p.127.
[244] Gould, Stephen Jay, ‘The Return of the Hopeful Monster,’ Natural History, June/July 1977, p. 22, 24.
[245] Dawkins, A Devil’s Chaplain, op. cit., p.211-212.
[246] ibid, p. 212.
[247] ibid.
[248] Dennet, Daniel, ‘The Leibnizian Paradigm’, David L. Hull and Michael Ruse (ed.'s), The Philosophy of Biology (Oxford, 1998), p. 49.
[249] Denton, op. cit., p. 228, 315.
[250] Dembski, William A., ‘Evolution’s Logic of Credulity: An unfettered response to Allen Orr’ at www.arn.org/docs/dembski/wd_logic_credulity.htm
[251] Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker, op. cit., p.146, 179, my italics.
[252] Stone, David H., in John F. Ashton, (ed.), On the Seventh Day, op. cit., p.90.
[253] Johnson, Phillip, ‘Daniel Dennett’s Dangerous Idea’, in Objection Sustained (Downers Grove: IVP, 1998), p. 62.
[254] Denton, Nature’s Destiny, op. cit., p.356.
[255] Harold, F., The Way of the Cell: Molecules, Organisms and the Order of Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001).
[256] Denton, op. cit., p.331.
[257] Johnson, Phillip, ‘What is Darwinism?’, in Objection Sustained, (Downers Grove: IVP, 1998), p. 23.
[258] Dawkins, A Devil’s Chaplain, op. cit., p.212.
[259] Wolf, Jakob, ‘Two Kinds of Causality – Philosophical Reflections on Darwin’s Black Box’ at www.iscid.org/ubb/ultimatebb.php?ubb=get_topic;f=10;t=000040
[260] ibid. cf. Howard Glicksman, ‘Wired for much more than Sound: Part IV: Vision Part 1 – Parts of the eye’ @ www.arn.org/docs/glicksman/eyw_041001.htm
[261] Dembski, No Free Lunch, op. cit., p.290.
[262] Darwin, Charles, Origin of Species, (1872), 6th edition, (New York University Press, 1988), p. 154.
[263] Dawkins, Richard, ‘Universal Darwinism’, in Hull and Ruse (ed.'s), The Philosophy of Biology, op. cit., p.29.
[264] Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker, op. cit., p.91.
[265] ibid.
[266] Piggliucci, ‘Design Yes, Intelligent No’, Darwin, Design, And Public Education, p. 467.
[267] ibid, p. 471.
[268] ibid, p. 467.
[269] ibid.
[270] Paley, William, Natural Theology @ www.hti.umich.edu/cgi/p/pd-modeng/pd-modeng-idx?type=HTML&rgn=DIV1&byte=53054870
[271] cf. Dembski, William A., No Free Lunch (Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield, 2002), p.279-289.
[272] Smart, John A., ‘On the Application of Irreducible Complexity’ at www.iscid.org/papers/Smart_ApplicationOfIC_060503.pdf
[273] Behe, Michael J., Dembski, Michael A. and Meyer, Stephen C., Science and Evidence for Design in the Universe (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1999), 13-14.
[274] Dennet, Daniel C., Darwin’s Dangerous Idea (London: Penguin, 1995), p.318.
[275] ibid, p. 317.
[276] Taylor, op cit, p. 118.
[277] ibid, p 119.
[278] Behe, Darwin’s Black Box, op. cit., p.39.
[279] Gene, Mike, ‘Irreducible Complexity and Darwinian Pathways’ at www.arn.org/docs/behe/mb_mg1darwinianpathways.htm
[280] Darwin, Origin of Species, op. cit., p 184.
[281] Dawkins, ‘Darwin Triumphant’, A Devil’s Chaplain, op. cit., p.86.
[282] Behe, op. cit., p. 40.
[283] Dembski, William A., ‘Irreducible Complexity Revisited’ @
www.designinference.com/documents/2004.01.Irred_Compl_Revisited.pdf
[284] Dembski, ‘Irreducible Complexity Revisited’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2004.01.Irred_Compl_Revisited.pdf
[285] Koons, op cit, p. 14.
[286] Darwin, Charles, Origin of Species, (1872), 6th edition, (New York University Press, 1988), p. 154.
[287] ibid.
[288] Koons, ‘Are Probabilities Indispensable to the Design Inference?’ @ www.utexas.edu/cola/depts/philosophy/faculty/koons/ontocomplex.pdf
[289] Behe, Michael J., ‘Molecular Machines: Experimental Support for the Design Inference’ at www.arn.org/docs/behe/mb_mm92496.htm
[290] Behe, Darwin’s Black Box, op. cit., p.194.
[291] ‘Self-Assembly of Bacterial Flagella’ at www.aip.org/mgr/png/2002/174.htm
[292] Dembski, William A., ‘Reinstating Design Within Science’, in Jay Wesley Richards (ed.), Unapologetic Apologetics (Downers Grove: IVP, 2001), p.253.
[293] Behe, op. cit., p.72.
[294] Macnab, Robert M., CRC Critical Reviews in Biochemistry, Vol. 5, Dec. 1978, p.291-341, quoted at www.parentcompany.com/design_kit/dek1d.htm
[295] ‘Here’s the recipe for making a just-so story . . . survey the biological world for structures/functions. Find those that seem useful for coming up with a precursor to the system in question and patch them together without much regard for biochemical and/or genetic details. Place the patchwork in an imaginary creature from the distant past that has conveniently gone extinct. Invoke a vague selective pressure that selects for the patchwork and then imagine it is plastic and amenable to further selective modification that just happens to arrive at the system in question.’ – Julie Thomas, quoted by Mike Gene, ‘Evolving the Bacterial Flagellum Through Cooption’ at www.idthink.net/biot/flag1/
[296] Dennet, Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, op. cit., p.521.
[297] TTSS secrete proteins to establish symbiotic relationships with eukaryotic cells.
[298] Dembski, William A., ‘The Bacterial Flagellum: Still Spinning Just Fine’ at www.designinference.com/documents/2003.02.Miller_Response.htm
[299] Gene, Mike, ‘Evolving the Bacterial Flagellum through Mutation and Co-option’ @ www.idthink.net/biot/flag1/index.html cf. Minnich, Scott A. & Michael J. Behe, ‘Genetic Analysis of Coordinate Flagellar and Type II Regulatory Circuits in Pathogenic Bacteria ’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=148
[300] Dembski, op cit, p. 3. ‘The type III system itself most likely evolved from a flagellum.’ – Mike Gene, ‘Evolving the Bacterial Flagellum through Mutation and Co-option’, ibid. cf. Minnich, Scott A. & Michael J. Behe, ‘Genetic Analysis of Coordinate Flagellar and Type II Regulatory Circuits in Pathogenic Bacteria ’ @ www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?id=148
[301] Orr, H. Allen, Boston Review.
[302] Thornhill, R. H. and Ussery, D. W., ‘A classification of possible routes of Darwinian evolution’, Journal of Theoretical Biology (2000) 203, p. 111-116.
[303] Minnich, Scott, in the video Unlocking the Mystery of Life.
[304] Dembski, op cit.
[305] Gene, Mike, ‘Irreducible Complexity and Darwinian Pathways’ at www.arn.org/docs/behe/mb_mg1darwinianpathways.htm
[306] Smart, ‘On the Application of Irreducible Complexity’, op. cit.
[307] Dembski, op cit.
[308] ibid.
[309] ibid.
[310] Minnich, op cit.
[311] cf. www.iscid.org/pcid.php
[312] Bracht, J. R., ‘The Bacterial Flagellum: A Response to Ursula Goodenough’ at www.iscid.org/papers/Bracht_GoodenoughResponse_021203.pdf
[313] ibid.
[314] Dembski, William A., ‘Gauging Intelligent Design’s Success’ at www.designinference.com/documents/2003.11.Gauging_IDs_Success.pdf
[315] Dembski, ‘The Bacterial Flagellum: Still Spinning Just Fine’, op. cit.
[316] Dembski, William A., ‘Irreducible Complexity Revisited’
[317] ibid.
[318] ibid.
[319] ibid.
[320] ibid.
[321] ibid.
[322] ibid.
[323] ibid.
[324] ibid.
[325] ibid.
[326] ibid.
[327] ibid.
[328] ibid.
[329] Dembski, William A., Intelligent Design (Downers Grove: IVP, 1999), p.149.
[330] Dembski, ‘Irreducible Complexity Revisited’, op cit.
[331] Dembski, William A., The Intelligent Design Revolution (Downers Grove: IVP, 2004), p. 112-113.
[332] ibid, p. 113.
[333] ibid, p. 112-113.
[334] Dembski, The Intelligent Design Revolution, op cit, p. 113. cf. Axe, Douglas, ‘Extreme Functional Sensitivity to Conservative Amino Acid Changes on Enzyme Exteriors’ @ www.mrc-cpe.cam.ac.uk/publications/axe_jmb_2000.pdf
[335] Behe, op cit, p. 40.
[336] Dembski, ‘Gauging Intelligent Design’s Success’, op. cit. cf. ‘Three Frequently Asked Questions About Intelligent Design’, op. cit. and Axe, ‘Extreme Functional Sensitivity to Conservative Amino Acid Changes on Enzyme Exteriors’, op. cit.
[337] Darwin, Charles, Origin of Species, (1872), 6th edition, (New York University Press, 1988), p. 154.
[338] Wakefield, Mary, ‘The Mystery of the Missing Links’ @ www.arn.org/docs2/news/missinglinkmystery102803.htm
(Dawkins made similar but distinct
comments about young earth creationists in a Guardian article @ www.guardian.co.uk/Archive/Article/0,4273,4371166,00.html - cf. Peter S. Williams, ‘Dawkins Ad Hominem - Misrepresented Again?’ @ www.arn.org/docs/williams/pw_misrepresentedagain.htm
[339] Reppert, Victor, C.S. Lewis’s Dangerous Idea, (IVP, 2003), p. 116.
[340] ARN guide to Evolution @ www.arn.org/docs/pbsevolution/vguide.pdf
[341] Dubay, The Evidential Power of Beauty, op cit, p. 322.
[342] Crews, Frederick, ‘Saving us from Darwin’, New York Review of Books.
[343] Dembski, William A., ‘What Every Theologian Should Know about Creation, Evolution, and Design’ @ www.arn.org/docs/dembski/wd_theologn.htm
[344] cf. ARN guide to Evolution, op cit.
[345] The fossil record does not reveal a gradual development from simple to more complex species with numerous intermittent forms as Darwin predicted: ‘the record reveals the sudden appearance at differing times of information-rich organisms within a hierarchical diversity of species with apparently no precursors.’ – Francis J. Beckwith, Law, Darwinism, and Public Education: The Establishment Clause and the Challenge of Intelligent Design, (Rowman & Littlefield, 2003), p. 118.
[346] cf. Stephen C. Meyer, Paul A. Nelson & Paul Chein, ‘The Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang’ @ www.discovery.org/articleFiles/PDFs/Cambrian.pdf
[347] Dembski, op cit, p. 231.
[348] Dawkins, ‘BLUEPRINTS Solving the Mystery of Evolution, by Maitland A. Edey and Donald C. Johanson’ @ www.world-of-dawkins.com/Dawkins/Work/Reviews/1989-04-09review_blueprint.shtml
[349] ibid.
[350] ibid.
[351] Dawkins, ‘Darwin Triumphant’, A Devil’s Chaplin, op cit, p. 81.
[352] ibid.
[353] ibid, p. 79, 81 & 84, my italics.
[354] ibid, p. 81.
[355] This is what ID theorists tend to mean by ‘Darwinism’: belief in ‘the fact of evolution itself’ wedded to a philosophical commitment to the explanatory sufficiency of natural processes (usually expressed as the multi-faceted theory that life arose millions of years ago by purely natural processes and then diversified from a common ancestor over millions of years through the undirected but non-random survival of small random hereditary changes).
[356] W.R. Thompson, introduction to Charles Darwin, The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, (New York: Dutton, 1967), pp. xxii.
[357] Lee Strobel, The Case for Faith, (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 2000), p. 90.
[358] Gordon Graham, Genes: A Philosophical Inquiry, (London: Routledge, 2002), p ix.
[359] ibid, p. 91.
[360] David Stove, quoted by Graham, ibid, p 31.
[361] ibid.
[363] Norman L. Geisler and Joseph Holden, Living Loud: Defending Your Faith, (Nashville, Tennessee: Broadman and Holman Publishers, 2002), p. 55.
[364] William Lane Craig, ‘Tough Questions About Science’, in Ravi Zacharias & Norman L. Geisler (ed.’s), Who Made God?, (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 2003), p. 70.
[365] Alvin Plantinga, ‘When Faith and Reason Clash: Evolution and the Bible’ @ www.asa3.org/ASA/dialogues/Faith-reason/CRS9-91Plantinga1.html
[366] Dawkins, A Devil’s Chaplain, op cit, p. 220.
[367] Jonathan Wells, ‘The Intelligent Design Movement, Evangelical Scientists, and the Future of Biology,’ in Darwinism Defeated?, op cit, p. 137.
[368] Cliff Marsh, ‘Evolution: a theory in terminal decline?’, The Plain Truth, September-November 2002, p. 20.
[369] Michael Denton, quoted from his professional resume, cf. Woodward, op cit, p. 57.
[370] David Swift, Preface @ www.amazon.co.uk/exec/obidos/tg/stores/detail/-/books/0954358902/reviews/026-0080128-1826838
[373] cf. Mark Hartwig, ‘Those Annoying Discovery Polls’ @ www.arn.org/docs/wedge/mh_wedge_031029.htm
[374] Paul Davies, Superforce, (Touchstone Books, 1985), p. 243.
[375] Paul Davies, The Cosmic Blueprint, (London: Harper Collins, 1989), p. 203.
[376] Paul Davies, The Fifth Miracle: The Search for the Origin of Life, (London: Penguin Press, 1998), p. xvi.
[377] ibid, p. xvi-xvii.
[378] ibid, p. xvii.
[379] ibid.
[380] ibid, p. xviii.
[381] Wiker, ‘Does Science Point to God?’, op cit.
[382] Denis Alexander, Rebuilding the Matrix, (Oxford: Lion, 2001), p. 21.
[383] Phillip E. Johnson, The Right Questions, (Downers Grove: IVP, 2002), p. 80.
[384] Woodward, op cit, p. 253.
[385] Charles Darwin, quoted in N. C. Gillespie, Charles Darwin and the Problem of Creation, (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1979), p. 87.
[386] Charles Darwin, The Origin of Species, (Ware: Wordsworth Editions Limited, 1998), p. 363.
[387] Dembski, ‘Three Frequently Asked Questions About Intelligent Design’, op cit.
[388] Dembski, Intelligent Design, op cit, p. 113.
[389] Benjamin Wiker, Moral Darwinism, (Downers Grove: IVP, 2002), p. 295.
[390] Smart, op cit.
[391] Dembski, No Free Lunch, op cit, p. 246.
[392] Dembski, ‘On the Very Possibility of Intelligent Design’, The Creation Hypothesis, op cit, p. 132.
[393] Dembski, Intelligent Design, op cit, p. 113.
[394] ibid.
[395] Dembski, ‘Evolution’s Logic of Credulity: An Unfettered Response to Allen Orr’, op cit.
[396] ibid, my italics.
[397] Wiker, ‘Does Science Point to God?’, op cit.
[398] ibid.
[399] Dawkins, A Devil’s Chaplin, op cit, p. 58.
[400] Theodosius Dobzhansky, quoted by Wells, op cit, p. 329.
[401] Wells, ibid, p. 329.
[402] Dembski, Intelligent Design, op cit, p. 255.
[403] Wiker, op cit, p. 3.
[404] ibid, p. 319.
[405] cf. Scott Minnich Homepage @ www.ag.uidaho.edu/mmbb/p_minnich_s.htm; Scott Minnich, ‘Bacterial Flagella: A Paradigm for Design’ @ www.arn.org/arnproducts/videos/v021.htm; www.idurc.org/yale-minnich.html; www.iscid.org/scott-minnich.php
[406] Dembski, op cit, p. 256-257.
[407] Woodward, op cit, p. 210.
[408] Jerry Bergman, ‘The Functions of Introns: From Junk DNA to Designed DNA’ @ www.asa3.org/ASA/PSCF/2001/PSCF9-01Bergman.html
[409] ibid. cf. Paul Nesselroade, ‘The Case of the Pseudogenes’ @ www.arn.org/docs/wedge/pn_wedge_030523.htm
Justin Gillis, ‘”Junk DNA” Contains Essential Information’ @ www.arn.org/docs2/news/junkdnaessential120802.htm
[411] William A. Dembski, ‘Becoming a Disciplined Science: Prospects, Pitfalls, and a Reality Check for ID’ @ www.arn.org/docs/dembski/wd_disciplinedscience.htm
[412] William A. Dembski, ‘Ten Question To Ask Your Biology Teacher’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2004.01.Ten_Questions_ID.pdf
[413] Dembski, Intelligent Design, op cit, p. 255-256.
[414] Jonathan Wells, ‘Jonathan Wells Lecture Report from Western Michigan University’ @ www.arn.org/docs/wells/jw_reportfromwmu031401.htm
[415] cf. Dembski, ‘Becoming a Disciplined Science’, op cit.
[416] William A. Dembski, ‘Paul Gross’s Dilemma: An Open Letter to the National Association of Scholars in Response to Paul Gross’s Article on Intelligent Design in the NAS’s September 2003 Issue of Science Insights’ @ www.designinference.com/documents/2003.09.Gross_Response.pdf
[417] Paul Davies, quoted by Witham, By Design, (San Francisco: Encounter Books, 2003), p. 149.
[419] Dembski, The Design Revolution, op cit, p. 305.
[420] Huston Smith, quoted on the front cover of On the Seventh Day, op cit, front cover quote.